Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

Skip to comments.

In Search of Deep Time: Beyond the Fossil Record to a New History of Life
Book | 1999 | Henry Gee

Posted on 06/09/2003 9:42:52 AM PDT by FairWitness

Why did the dinosaurs become extinct? Why did fishes evolve legs and learn to walk on land? How did birds become airborne? Is humanity the culmination of evolution? Apart from their perennial fascination, questions like these--evolutionary questions, about 'how' and 'why'--are united by an implication of a narrative in which cause and effect are linked: dinosaurs became extinct because of the after-effects of an asteroid impact, or because they were rendered obsolete by mammals. Chains of cause and effect may also be animated by purpose: fishes evolved legs for walking on land; birds evolved feathers for flight; human beings evolved from apelike ancestors because they had bigger brains, could make tools and use language.

Popular views of science assume that cause, effect and purpose can be easily discerned. Hardly a day goes by without reports of discoveries of genes for homosexuality, good motherhood, breast cancer or alcoholism; of the bones of ancestors and 'missing links'; of explanations of why the elephant evolved its trunk; or warning that a certain food item causes a particular disease. Many of the assumptions we make about evolution, especially concerning the history of life as understood from the fossil record, are, however, baseless.

The reason for this lies with the scale of geological time that scientists are dealing with, which is so vast that it defies narrative. Fossils, such as the fossils that we hail as our ancestors, constitute primary evidence for the history of life, but each fossil is an infinitesimal dot, lost in the fathomless sea of time, whose relationship with other fossil and organisms living in the present day is obscure. Any story that we tell against the compass of geological time that links these fossils in sequences of cause and effect--or ancestry and descent--is, therefore, only ours to make. We invent these stories, after the fact, to justify the history of life according to our own prejudices. Nobody will ever know what caused the extinction of the dinosaurs, because we weren't there to watch it happen. All we have are two isolated observations--the apparent absence of dinosaurs 65 million years ago, and evidence for a catastrophic phenomenon, such as the impact of an asteroid, at around the same time. There can be no certain link between the two. Geological time admits no narrative in which causes can be linked with effects.

Fossils are never found with labels or certificates of authenticity. You can never know that the fossil bone you might dig up in Africa belonged to your direct ancestor, or anyone else's. The attribution of ancestry does not come from the fossil; it can only come from us. Fossils are mute: their silence gives us unlimited licence to tell their stories for them, which usually takes the form of chains of ancestry and descent. These stories are like history, of events leading to other events; of succession and defeats; change and stability. Such tales are sustained more in our minds than in reality and are informed and conditioned by our own prejudices, which will tell us not what really happened, but what we think ought to have happened. If there are 'missing links', they exist only in our imaginations.

John McPhee, an eloquent writer on geology, coined the term 'Deep Time' to distinguish geological time from the scale of time that governs our everyday lives. McPhee meant the term to refer to the immense intervals, measured in millions of years, discussed as if they were days or weeks in the conversation of geologists: yet in reality, the intervals of geological time are too long to be readily comprehensible to minds used to thinking in terms of days, weeks and years--decades at most.

< "snip" to omit a table outlining formal divisions of geological time, in millions of years >

After presenting a chart of geological time and impressing you with its scale, canonical accounts of the history of life consider that their duty towards Deep Time has been fulfilled and will move on to telling the story of life as if it were Hamlet: a drama that can be understood in human terms. We will learn of the origin and evolution of life; the rise and fall of the fishes and the fall of the dinosaurs; the evolution of the birds and mammals, the primates, and finally Man. Each species will make its entry and exit like an actor on the stage, with Deep Time as the backdrop.

But apart from telling you that Deep Time is long, conventional accounts never consider the implications of the scale of Deep time on the way we think about evolution. If, as McPhee says, Deep Time implies intervals more or less incomprehensible to humans, we are entitled to ask whether it is valid to tell stories about evolution according to the conventions of narrative or drama. If it is not, then every story we tell in which causes are linked with effects, and ancestors are linked with descendants, becomes questionable: we can no longer use Deep Time as a backdrop for the stories we tell ourselves about evolution, and how and why we came to be who we are.

Once we realize that Deep Time can never support narratives of evolution, we are forced to accept that virtually everything we thought we knew about evolution is wrong. It is wrong because we want to think of the history of life as a story; but that is precisely what we cannot do. This tension--between Deep Time and the everyday scale of time--is the theme of this book. What we need is an antidote to the historical approach to the history of life--a kind of 'anti-history' that recognizes the special properties of Deep Time.

If we can never know for certain that any fossil we unearth is our direct ancestor, it is similarly invalid to pluck a string of fossils from Deep Time, arrange these fossils in chronological order, and assert that this arrangement represents a sequence of ancestry and descent. As Stephen Jay Gould has demonstrated, such misleading tales are part of popular iconography: everyone has seen pictures in which a sequence of fossil hominids--members of the human family of species--are arranged in an orderly procession from primitive forms up to modern Man. To complicate matters further, such sequences are justified after the fact by tales of inevitable, progressive improvement. For example, the evolution of Man is said to have been driven by improvements in posture, brain size, and the coordination between hand and eye, which led to technological achievements such as fire, the manufacture of tools and the use of language. But such scenarios are subjective. They can never be tested by experiment, and so they are unscientific. They rely for their currency not on scientific test, but on assertion and the authority of their presentation.

Given the ubiquitous chatter of journalists and headline writers about the search for ancestors, and the discovery of missing links, it may come as a surprise to learn that most professional paleontologists do not think of the history of life in terms of scenarios or narratives, and that they rejected the storytelling mode of evolutionary history as unscientific more than thirty years ago. Behind the scenes, in museums and universities, a quiet revolution has taken place.

The architects of this revolution sought ways to discover the pattern of the history of life that is free from subjective, untestable stories. If it is fair to assume that all life on Earth shares a common evolutionary origin, it follows that every organism that ever existed must be related to every other. We are all cousins. Every goanna and gourami is cousin of every gecko and ginkgo that has ever lived, or will live in the future. This must be true, even though we can neither tell who was whose direct ancestor or justify any scenarios to support assertions about ancestry and descent.

Before we can understand the history of life, we need to find the order in which we are all cousins, the topology or branching order of the tree of life. This can be done without having to make any prior assumptions about cause and effect, or ancestry and descent. These branching diagrams, which look , misleadingly like genealogies, are proper scientific hypotheses that can be tested by examining the strength or liklihood of alternative orders of branching--different orders of cousinhood--in the light of the anatomy of the organisms in whose relationship we are interested. As long ago as 1950, a German entomologist called Willi Hennig used these simple principles as a basis for a new way of looking at the living world. Hennig sought to understand creatures in terms of how they shared features with one another, independently of time, rather than in terms of their history of ancestry and descent. Hennig called his philosophy 'phylogenetic systematics', but it came to be known as 'cladistics' and its practitioners, inevitably, as 'cladists'. The branching diagrams cladists drew up to represent orders of cousinhood between organisms--patterns of relationship--became known as 'cladograms'.

Cladistics looks only at the pattern of the history of life, free from assumptions about the process of the unfolding of history. It resolves the conundrum of trying to comprehend Deep Time in terms of an unfolding drama. Because of this, cladistics is the best philosophy for the scientific understanding of the history of life as we unearth it from Deep Time. More than a set of techniques, but less than a science in its own right, cladistics is a way of 'seeing', of looking at the products of evolution as they are, and not how we would like them to be.

An important aspect of cladistics, as in all science, is testability. In cladistics, you are asked to find the most likely way in which a set of organisms is related to one another--to estimate, in other words, their relative degrees of cousinhood. This is done with a cladogram. As I show in chapter 1, if you have more than two organisms, you will find that there is more than one way of drawing a cladogram that links them up. What this means is choice: if there is more than one way in which organisms can be cousins, you are forced to consider the alternatives, and you must find a way of evaluating them all.

How can these alternatives be evaluated? The central test is as old as science--older: Occam's razor, or the Principle of Parsimony. That is, if you have to make a choice between explanations, you should choose the simplest. The simplest, or most 'parsimonious', cladogram is the one that assumes the smallest amount of evolutionary change. I'll discuss what that means for our understanding of evolution later in this book.

Conventional stories about evolution, about 'missing links', are not in themselves testable, because there is only one possible course of events--the one implied by the story. If your story is about how a group of fishes crawled onto land and evolved legs, you are forced to see this as a once-only event, because that's the way the story goes. You can either subscribe to the story or not--there are no alternatives. In cladistics, you can put the story to the test, by studying the fossils and asking yourself how they might have been related to one another. A fossil fish you happen to find might have been your direct ancestor, but you will never be able to establish the case, one way or the other.

Such study might turn up some surprises. For example, your evidence might show that more than one group of fishes crawled ashore independently, or that other groups of fishes evolved legs, but stayed underwater. By offering choices, cladistics opens our eyes to surprising new discoveries and possibilities of evolution otherwise hidden from us. Conventional wisdom has fishes crawling ashore, evolving limbs, and progressing, inexorably, to amphibians, to reptiles, to mammals, and to Man. Cladistics suggests that things might have been otherwise.

Testability is a central feature of the activity we call science. Some have sought a kind of special dispensation for paleontology as an 'historical' science, that it be admitted to the high table of science even though paleontologists cannot, classically, do the kinds of experiments other scientists take for granted. You cannot go back in time to watch the dinosaurs become extinct or fishes crawl from the slime to become amphibians. More pointedly, you cannot, as Stephen Jay Gould discussed in his book Wonderful Life, go back in time to see what other things might have happened instead, had circumstances been slightly different. What if the asteroid missed Earth, sparing the dinosaurs? What would have happened if the fishes decided to stay underwater after all? In either case, would we be here? We cannot see what nature would have done had she been able to rerun the tape of evolution: were we able to witness such a re-run, would the outcome be different from what we see, as Gould argues, or very much the same? In strict scientific terms, such questions are meaningless. The problem is that what we see before us is the result of a once-only experiment in history. Because it happened only once, it is not subject to the reproducibility scientists usually require. This is not possible in paleontology except in our imaginations.

However, paleontology is either scientific, or it is not, and you may ask whether the particular problems that paleontology has with its subject--Deep Time--should be allowed to mitigate its inability to reproduce experiments in the approved scientific manner. They should not. To see paleontology as in any way 'historical' is a mistake in that it assumes that untestable stories have scientific value. But we already know that Deep Time does not support statements based on connected narrative, so to claim that paleontology can be seen as an historical science is meaningless: if the dictates of Deep Time are followed, no science can ever be historical.

Paleontology read as history is additionally unscientific because, without testable hypotheses, its statements rely for their justification on authority, as if its practitioners had privileged access to absolute truth--'truth which can be known', in the words of the late paleontologist and cladist Donn Rosen (whose views are discussed in chapter 5). Whether you believe the conventional wisdom that our own species Homo sapiens descended in seamless continuity from the preexisting species Homo erectus depends not on the evidence (because the fossil evidence is moot) but on the deferment of your lack of knowledge to the authority of the presenter or whether the presentation of the evidence resonates with your prejudices. The assumption of authority is profoundly, mischievously, and dangerously unscientific. It conflicts with how we are taught science from our earliest years, that the scientific method should be rigorously democratic; that statements from authorities in a field should be as subject to scrutiny as those emanating from the most humble sources, even a beginning student. Nobody should be afraid to ask a silly question.

Cladistics has remained true to this simple view of science. When, as a student, I spent a summer working on fossil fishes at the Natural History Museum in London, my innocent views were accorded the same respect had they come from the head of the Fossil Fish Section, the late Colin Patterson, one of the world's most respected workers on fossil fishes, and one of the most influential advocates for cladistics. As I discuss in chapter 5, Patterson wished to replace the elitist, authoritarian presentation of old-fashioned museum displays with an approach to science that encouraged the participation of a wider audience, represented by the museum-going public. My opinion received equal value because Patterson, for all his eminence, had no special access to the truth that would be denied to me.

The story of human interaction with fossils represents an example of how experience and belief have a powerful effect on interpretation and demonstrates why scientific truths can only be temporary. Today, we see fossils as the remains of creatures that once lived. However, this nature is not inherent in the fossils. It is our immersion in a century and a half of Darwinian thought, not the fossils themselves, that gives us the capacity to see fossils as kin to things that were once as alive as you or I. If this were not the case, we would interpret fossils differently. In societies without science in the sense that we would understand it today, fossils were seen as signs of divine or diabolical action, as the bones of giants or the teeth of dragons, or as the bones of creatures that perished in Noah's flood. Observers innocent of science, ignorant of religious or cultural tradition, and incapable of imagination would no doubt see fossils only as rocks. All these views could be as valid to their respective beholders as the apprehension of fossils as the remains of living organisms is to us. We cannot be certain, therefore, that our current understanding of fossils is not as provisional as these earlier ones.

This line of reasoning appeals to contemporary philosophers and critics who regard with detachment the conventional claims of scientists to be rolling back the frontiers of ignorance, unveiling universal truths, and so on. Such critics suggest, instead, that what scientists find out is conditioned at least as much by their cultural heritage as by objective reality. It is hard to argue with this point of view, borne out, for example, by the way our approach to fossils has changed over the ages. Looking at science from this perspective, you might ask whether cladistics itself--in its embrace of patterns of relationship rather than lines of ancestry, and its insistence on truths that are relative and provisional rather than absolute and final--falls foul of these contemporary prejudices.

The answer must be no. Cladistics is, in truth, somewhat reactionary in that it embodies a purist attitude to science that seeks to establish traditional, scientific values such as the importance of objectivity, the testability of hypotheses, and the provisional nature of the results of such tests. A cladist might say that the whole of science ought to be similarly austere, in that those scientists who claim to unveil universal truths have no business making such claims in the name of science.

Without cladistics, paleontology is no more science than the one that proclaimed that Earth was 6000 years old, and flat--and thenhad the effrontery to claim divine sanction for this view.

Henry Gee, the author, has a B.Sc. in zoology and genetics from the University of Leeds, and a Ph.D. in zoology from the University of Cambridge. He is a senior editor for Nature and "spends most of his time as a manuscript editor specializing in evolutionary and comparative biology". Though he is firmly devoted to "cladistics", in which all species, fossil or living, are "on the top row and ancestor/descendent relationships are not postulated", he is equally firmly devoted to Darwinian evolution in which all species are "related by common descent".


TOPICS: Culture/Society; Miscellaneous
KEYWORDS: cladistics; crevolist; evolution; species
Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first 1-2021-23 next last
The book from which the introductory chapter is reproduced above is a "what it is and how it works" description not a "how to do it" method.

I thought the "Introduction" worth reproducing here for its emphasis that what is important in biology is understanding "patterns of relationship rather than lines of ancestry" (even though Gee periodically slips into the evolution/ancestry mode). To understand and appreciate biology, it is critical to understand that all life is related on the cellular and molecular level - in that sense we are "all one creation" whether you believe in a Creator or not. As far as I am concerned I don't care if a Doctor "believes in evolution" as long as he or she thoroughly understands the biochemistry, physiology, anatomy and pharmacology that is first studied and described in animals and then refined in human clinical studies

1 posted on 06/09/2003 9:42:52 AM PDT by FairWitness
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
From a book review by Anthony Campbell:
"His main argument, which he makes repeatedly throughout the book, is that what might be called the family tree approach to palaeontology, in which fossils are arranged in a developmental sequence that purports to tell a story about how evolution occurred, is unscientific. Fossils are what they are; they don't come with a pedigree and it is impossible to say which are ancestral to which. Even though we may know that fossil A is older than fossil B, because it comes from a deeper geological layer, this does not negate the possibility that species B was really ancestral to species A. Alternatively, there may be no question of ancestry at all; the two organisms may simply have been cousins (all organisms on the planet are, ultimately, related to one another). Claims for developmental sequences are untestable and rest ultimately on the authority of the person who makes the claim, and this, according to Gee, is unscientific."

The author writes, as an example of a significant consequence of using cladistics to look at nature, "Historically, fish represent a group of equal status with reptiles and amphibians." But the - - "fishes do not form a natural group . . . the term 'fish' has no zoological meaning, as a category".

2 posted on 06/09/2003 9:50:23 AM PDT by FairWitness
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
Before we can understand the history of life, we need to find the order in which we are all cousins, the topology or branching order of the tree of life. This can be done without having to make any prior assumptions about cause and effect, or ancestry and descent. These branching diagrams, which look , misleadingly like genealogies, are proper scientific hypotheses that can be tested by examining the strength or liklihood of alternative orders of branching--different orders of cousinhood--in the light of the anatomy of the organisms in whose relationship we are interested. As long ago as 1950, a German entomologist called Willi Hennig used these simple principles as a basis for a new way of looking at the living world. Hennig sought to understand creatures in terms of how they shared features with one another, independently of time, rather than in terms of their history of ancestry and descent. Hennig called his philosophy 'phylogenetic systematics', but it came to be known as 'cladistics' and its practitioners, inevitably, as 'cladists'. The branching diagrams cladists drew up to represent orders of cousinhood between organisms--patterns of relationship--became known as 'cladograms'.

How exactly does this differ from what Linnaeus did two centuries earlier?

3 posted on 06/09/2003 9:57:17 AM PDT by inquest
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
read later
4 posted on 06/09/2003 10:04:42 AM PDT by LiteKeeper
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness; blam; Carry_Okie
ping and bump
5 posted on 06/09/2003 10:05:41 AM PDT by farmfriend ( Isaiah 55:10,11)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
John McPhee, an eloquent writer on geology, coined the term 'Deep Time'

McPhee is a fine writer, and perhaps he deserves credit for coining this term. But it does remind me of J.R.R. Tolkien who (IIRC) reported that Elendil's sword Narsil was forged by the Elven smith Telchar "in the deeps of time".

6 posted on 06/09/2003 10:06:05 AM PDT by ClearCase_guy
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: inquest
How exactly does this differ from what Linnaeus did two centuries earlier?

Linnaeus did not have a computer to sort through the myriad possibilities available for relationships?

7 posted on 06/09/2003 10:09:45 AM PDT by FairWitness
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 3 | View Replies]

To: ClearCase_guy
Elendil's sword Narsil was forged by the Elven smith Telchar "in the deeps of time".

Good catch!

8 posted on 06/09/2003 10:10:38 AM PDT by FairWitness
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 6 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
deep bias - evolution - ideology - Reason -- KNOWLEDGE // philosphy -- tecchnology // science ==> creation !
9 posted on 06/09/2003 10:19:05 AM PDT by f.Christian (( apocalypsis, from Gr. apokalypsis, from apokalyptein to uncover, from apo- + kalyptein to cover))
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 8 | View Replies]

To: f.Christian
You may have something interesting to say, but in the form you are doing it you are talking to yourself as far as I can tell.
10 posted on 06/09/2003 10:21:25 AM PDT by FairWitness
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 9 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
deep bias <== evolution - ideology - Reason -- KNOWLEDGE // philosphy -- tecchnology // science ==> creation !
11 posted on 06/09/2003 10:22:33 AM PDT by f.Christian (( apocalypsis, from Gr. apokalypsis, from apokalyptein to uncover, from apo- + kalyptein to cover))
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 10 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
Cladologism aside, the era of biological evolution is essentially over due to our present state of existence in a very tiny segment of time. All current evolution is now of our doing and mainly exists in the social system. The Teilhard noosphere, if you like. The history of evolution of the noosphere could use the services of a competent cladologist.
12 posted on 06/09/2003 10:29:18 AM PDT by RightWhale (gazing at shadows)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 2 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
Why did the dinosaurs become extinct?
Maybe their DNA stopped replicating. Everything is finite. Nothing lasts forever.

Why did fishes evolve legs and learn to walk on land?


So that when they die, they can sleep with the people.

How did birds become airborne?


Something about the shape of their wings and the air passing over/under them.

Is humanity the culmination of evolution?


If there is culmination, then we are still culminating. If there is evolution, then God created it like he created everything else.
13 posted on 06/09/2003 10:31:38 AM PDT by Consort
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: RightWhale
Cladologism aside, the era of biological evolution is essentially over due to our present state of existence in a very tiny segment of time.

I would hesitate to say it is over. Think of the "Flatland" analogy where the third dimension is missing. For us, in our very brief lifetimes, the fourth dimension is missing. Sure we experience time, but compared to "deep time" our time dimension is paper thin like the third dimension in Flatland. We may drastically affect evolution by hastening the demise of species but the next million or billion years may bring things we cannot imagine (and don't have to worry about whether we can imagine or not).

14 posted on 06/09/2003 10:40:40 AM PDT by FairWitness
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 12 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
bump
15 posted on 06/09/2003 10:47:09 AM PDT by GOPJ
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness
Our genes cause changes in us as we grow up and as we grow older as individuals. Our human genome causes changes in the whole human race over time and we are undergoing a major genetic event which is the dawn of the clone.
16 posted on 06/09/2003 10:50:01 AM PDT by Consort
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: inquest
How exactly does this differ from what Linnaeus did two centuries earlier?

Linnaeus lacked several hundred thousand fossils that have been dug up since his lifetime, genomes for determining closeness of relationship at the DNA level, and a century of genetic research that studies the rather remarkable structural changes that can result from single mutations. Among other things.

Like asking the difference between B.F. Goodrich dropping a bit of rubber on the stove and Michelin designing your next set of tires.

17 posted on 06/09/2003 11:09:56 AM PDT by js1138
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 3 | View Replies]

To: js1138
Michio Kaku thinks that DNA changes 1% every million years. So if our DNA is 30% similar to corn, how long ago did corn and we split up?
18 posted on 06/09/2003 11:13:51 AM PDT by RightWhale (gazing at shadows)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 17 | View Replies]

To: RightWhale
Michio Kaku thinks that DNA changes 1% every million years.

Statistics apply to broad catagories. They cannot be interpreted to reveal individual histories, any more than traffic statistics can be interpreted to reveal how many accidents or traffic tickets you have had.

19 posted on 06/09/2003 11:23:57 AM PDT by js1138
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 18 | View Replies]

To: FairWitness; *crevo_list
Deep Time Bookmark
20 posted on 06/09/2003 11:28:48 AM PDT by forsnax5
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]


Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first 1-2021-23 next last

Disclaimer: Opinions posted on Free Republic are those of the individual posters and do not necessarily represent the opinion of Free Republic or its management. All materials posted herein are protected by copyright law and the exemption for fair use of copyrighted works.

Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

FreeRepublic, LLC, PO BOX 9771, FRESNO, CA 93794
FreeRepublic.com is powered by software copyright 2000-2008 John Robinson