Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

Skip to comments.

Camus as Conservative: A post 9/11 reassessment of the work of Albert Camus
Orthodoxy Today ^ | 12/20/03 | Murray Soupcoff

Posted on 12/20/2003 12:47:34 PM PST by bdeaner

Camus as Conservative: A post 9/11 reassessment of the work of Albert Camus

Murray Soupcoff

The Guardian -- that last fanatical bastion of English left-wing obstinacy and foolishness -- published a unique book review honouring the latest Penguin edition of The Plague, the enduring fictional allegory of human suffering and sacrifice, written by French existentialist novelist Albert Camus.

It was particularly surprising that The Guardian, of all publications, would publish what was really a revised introduction to the latest English-language edition of The Plague, since Camus' unique philosophical and political point of view was always so different from that of most of today's Guardian contributors.

Like many other European intellectual heirs of Heidegger at the end of World War II, Camus philosophically travelled to the very edge of the ontological abyss and resolutely confronted a black Nietzschean vision of the death of God and the end of all conventional morality (a bleak vision sparked by the horrors of the Nazi era and the complicity of so many "ordinary" citizens in the cruelties of the holocaust). But unlike such existentialist contemporaries as Jean Paul Sartre, Camus did not cope with the "anxiety", "nausea" and "dread" that accompanied this nihilistic vision by taking refuge in the most popular left-wing "isms" of his day.

As reviewer Tony Judd appropriately noted in his Guardian piece, Camus' point of view in The Plague is particularly worth careful study after the events of 9/11. If nothing else, it demonstrates that if he had somehow still been alive on the day of that terrorist nightmare, he -- unlike most leftist thinkers of yesterday and today -- would have had no problem making judgements about who was at fault and why. And it is very unlikely that he would have been tempted to justify (or rationalize) the horrific actions of al-Qaeda by proffering the well-worn slander, so popular on the Continent, that the United States somehow deserved what it got.

Of course, there's no doubt that Camus was definitely a man of the political left. He had been raised in grinding poverty in Algeria. And he was briefly a member of the Communist Party in pre-War Algeria. But unlike Sartre and his pampered middle-class friends, Camus didn't existentially seek an awareness of "being" by means of a dogmatic ideological mission to redress human misery through the totalitarian Stalinist revolutionary solution (with all the doublethink and violence this ideological undertaking involved). Instead, Camus -- to use his mode of expression -- "revolted" against the "no" in life by embracing the "yes" in existence.

Camus would not take the easy way out intellectually, by abandoning all notions of morality and ethics in politics for the sake of the ultimate good (the revolution). Unlike Sartre and company, he rejected the era's most beckoning diversion from the phenomenological nihilist nightmare -- an intellectual fun ride on the deterministic Marxist roller coaster of historical inevitability, an intellectual adventure during which one immersed oneself in the extremes of a historical dialectic in which the end (the revolution) justified any means (murder, show trials and the extermination of all who get in the way).

As existentialists, intellectual contemporaries such as Sartre may well have attempted to confront the angst-inducing vision of the godless, nihilistic hellhole that represented "existence" for free thinkers in post-Nazi Europe. However, Sartre and his followers flinched. They turned away from this depressing nightmare, and found an escape from free will in the siren call of the dialectical "historical" struggle and all the comforting certainties (and rigidities) that the Stalinist strain of Communism offered them at the time. And by throwing themselves into the pursuit of the revolutionary end, they and their myriad compatriots in the class struggle were freed to pursue any means. In their minds, they and political idols like Stalin were unrestrained by the limits of everyday morality from pursuing the extremes of human cruelty that the revolutionary mission might demand.

In the class struggle, they could find "meaning" and "aliveness" in being. They could experience a Nietzschean "vitality" that only intellectual Ubermensches of revolutionary culture like themselves could truly appreciate. And through the struggle for revolution, they could transcend the empty nothingness of everyday bourgeois existence that so upset them.

Camus too came face to face with the same nihilistic vision that bedeviled most European freethinkers in the aftermath of World War II -- the dark, rootless path of constant suffering that was life, which ended only in the fear and trembling that attended godless death. But -- to use his language -- he "revolted" against this nihilistic dead end, the absurdity of existence that comprises the vale of tears of human life.

Instead of succumbing to the darkness of this nihilistic vision, by affirming the "no" in life, he turned to what he considered to be the "yes" in life -- the a-priori light of human existence: others. He said "yes" to the intrinsic sense of solidarity he experienced toward his fellow humans (no matter how imperfect they were), and otherwise strived to accept the unalterable "limitations" of human existence.

Rebellion for Camus was not the inhumane "ends-justifies-the-means" action demanded by the historical struggle for the perfect revolutionary social order -- with all the murderous extremes that such a struggle inevitably encompassed. Camus' notion of rebellion resisted the nihilistic call, by affirming the relatedness of self to others and to nature. One strived to accept the limitations of human existence, all the while savoring every joy in life and fighting against every private or civic action that brought unjust suffering to others.

For Camus, the true "rebel" embraced human solidarity, as both means and ends, in a continuing "revolt" against the nihilistic shadow. The rebel could feel most alive by transcending the nothingness of being and finding meaning in relatedness to his or her fellows. And within Camus' humanistic world view, even the unceasing dialectical march of revolutionary history had to come to a halt when confronted by the exigencies of an even more basic a-priori truth of existence -- each human's essential solidarity with and obligation to the other.

Of course, after wading through this somewhat arcane discussion, you're probably thinking by now: "So what? It's 2002. Why bother ourselves with outdated writings from more than 50 years ago? Why refight the philosophical and political battles of post-War Europe now?"

The answer is twofold. First of all, after a careful reading of Camus, it's not difficult to come to the conclusion that despite his life-long leftist political leanings, he was a philosophical conservative by nature. And secondly, he still remains one of the best intellectual antidotes for budding college-age intellects searching for "meaning" amidst the empty, sterile conformity that comprises life in contemporary capitalist society (in their minds anyway).

Camus is a cautionary literary and philosophical footnote to the post-Heidegger European intellectual quest that has bequeathed to us the intellectual poison of Foucault and Jacques Derrida, and the soul-destroying theorems of deconstruction. He is an energizing antidote to the paralyzing non-judgmentalism of post-modernist political thought that produced the strange ambivalence (if not satisfaction) of North American intellectuals regarding the events of 9/11.

As a man of political action, Albert Camus may have adopted the language and world view of European leftist politics as he battled against the social and political injustices of the 1940's and 1950's. But perhaps because his entire identity was so rooted in the practical, real-world sensibility of the working-class surroundings of his Algerian childhood, and his strong identification with the eternal rhythms of nature that dominated life in the seaside surroundings of his birthplace, Camus could not shake an intrinsic conservatism in his perception of the dynamics of change in human life. Consequently, in quasi-philosophical treatises like The Rebel, over and over again he cautioned even the most well-meaning social and political revolutionaries of the need to keep in mind the "limitations" of human existence -- the innate and enduring injustices of life and nature which mere human interventions could never alter (after all, life's greatest injustice may well be that we inevitably die).

Like some wise old conservative, even the youthful Camus seemed to have an instinctive skepticism about the perfectibility of man or his social institutions. And just like post-war conservatives in the U.S. (of whom he did not approve), he instinctively recognized the travesties of the great Stalinist experiment in revolutionary society that was the Soviet Union of the 1930s, '40s and '50's. He was appalled by the Stalinist show trials of the 1930's. He condemned the ruthlessness of the petty commissars and tyrants who flourished in the Communist revolutionary milieu of the 1930's and '40's. And unlike leftist European intellectual contemporaries like Sartre, he strenuously objected to the Soviets' ruthless suppression of the anti-communist Hungarian uprisings of 1956.

Most important, Camus' literary and philosophical writings offer an alternative intellectual magnet for today's disaffected young intellectuals. He addresses the sense of alienation and rebellion still experienced by today's idealistic young thinkers in the post-modern age, those stubborn young minds still trying to forge an "authentic" path amidst the absurdity and banality of what they view as modern living. Having confronted death in his many bouts with tuberculosis, and during his participation in the French resistance movement, Camus convincingly tackles the question of living authentically within the modern existential void. And yet unlike Heidegger's post-modernist successors, Camus rejects any escape into the moral relativism of post-structural nihilism.

For in the end, Camus recognizes the existence of good and evil in human life. And in his writings, as in his life, he tried his best to ally himself with the forces of good (the light), in the fight against the forces of evil (darkness). His was an intellectual voyage guided by an innate notion of the enduring pull of the other -- by the timeless call for human solidarity against the vicissitudes of existence.

Certainly, Camus would have understood and approved of the heroic sacrifice made by so many New York City firefighters and police on September 11th, 2001. And As Tony Judd noted in his Guardian review, The Plague in particular makes enlightening reading in the aftermath of the dramatic events of 9/11.

Consequently, I suggest you amble over to your nearest bookstore and pick up a paperback copy of Camus' novel The Plague and then his political-philosophical treatise The Rebel. Think of them as intellectual comfort food for these confusing times.

Even better, make a gift of The Plague (and perhaps Camus' cold tale of alienation, The Stranger) to some conflicted young person in college you're acquainted with. It may well serve as a surprising antidote to the poisonous cant currently being dished out to this unknowing victim by his or her post-modernist professors. Murray Soupcoff is a recovering liberal and webmaster of The Iconoclast website.


TOPICS: Culture/Society; Editorial; Philosophy
KEYWORDS: 911; albertcamus; alqaeda; anxiety; bookreview; camus; deathofgod; deconstruction; dread; existentialism; frenchintellectuals; friedrichnietzsche; jacquesderrida; jeanpaulsartre; literature; martinheidegger; marxism; michelfoucault; nausea; nihilism; postmodernism; september12era; theplague; therebel; thestranger; tonyjudd; wwii
Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first 1-2021-4041-6061-80 next last
Now here's an interpretation of Camus you're NOT likely to see in the academy!
1 posted on 12/20/2003 12:47:35 PM PST by bdeaner
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | View Replies]

To: bdeaner
True. But frankly, anyone who worries about all that poststructuralist trash is wasting his time. Heidegger caused endless trouble with his arcane nonsense. I rather liked Camus when I was in college, but the whole existentialist mind trip is a waste of time.

I'd recommend a nice little article entitled "The Secret that Leo Strauss Never Revealed, published in Asia Times by someone using the pen name of Spengler and posted her at:

http://www.freerepublic.com/focus/news/910008/posts

Here's an extract which sums up what I'm trying to say:




And yet there is the nagging problem of Heidegger, who rejected all tellers of absolute truth and Socrates most vehemently. As an impressionable young man, Strauss fell under Heidegger's influence and never quite shook it. Considering Heidegger's grandiose reputation, it is depressing to consider how cheap was the trick he played. What is Being?, he demanded of a generation that after the First World War felt the ground shaky under their feet. It is a shame that Eddie Murphy never studied philosophy, for then we might have had the following Saturday Night Live sketch about Heidegger's definition of Being with respect to Non-Being, namely death. The use of dialect would make Heidegger's meaning far clearer than in the available English translations:

"What be 'Be'? You cain't say that 'Be' be, cause you saying 'be' to talk about 'Be', and it don't mean nothing to say that 'Be' be dis or 'Be' be dat. 'Be' be 'Be' to begin wit'. So don't you be saying 'Be' be 'Be'. You wanna talk about 'Be', you gotta talk about what ain't be nothin' at all. You gotta say 'Be' be what ain't 'ain't-Be'. Now when you ain't be nothing at all? Dat be when you be daid. When you daid you ain't be nothing, you just be daid. So 'Be' be somewhere between where you be and where you ain't be, dat is, when you be daid. Any time you say 'Be' you is also saying 'ain't-Be', and dat make you think about being daid."

That is all there is to Heidegger's Existential idea of Being-towards-death. Metaphysical pettifogging of this sort appeals to people whom the disintegration of social order has made uncertain about their sense of being.
2 posted on 12/20/2003 1:17:11 PM PST by Cicero (Marcus Tullius)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: bdeaner
Killing an Arab - The Cure, 1980

Standing on a beach
With a gun in my hand
Staring at the sea
Staring at the sand
Staring down the barrel
At the arab on the ground
See his open mouth
But hear no sound

I'm alive
I'm dead
I'm the stranger
Killing an arab

I can turn and walk away
Or I can fire the gun
Staring at the sky
Staring at the sun
Whichever I choose
It amounts to the same

Absolutely nothing

I'm alive
I'm dead
I'm the stranger
Killing an arab

Feel the steel butt jump
Smooth in my hand
Staring at the sea
Staring at the sand
Staring at myself
Reflected in the eyes of
The dead man on the beach

The dead man
On the beach

I'm alive
I'm dead
I'm the stranger
Killing an arab
3 posted on 12/20/2003 1:19:42 PM PST by Chi-townChief
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: Cicero
"What be 'Be'? You cain't say that 'Be' be, cause you saying 'be' to talk about 'Be', and it don't mean nothing to say that 'Be' be dis or 'Be' be dat. 'Be' be 'Be' to begin wit'. So don't you be saying 'Be' be 'Be'. You wanna talk about 'Be', you gotta talk about what ain't be nothin' at all. You gotta say 'Be' be what ain't 'ain't-Be'. Now when you ain't be nothing at all? Dat be when you be daid. When you daid you ain't be nothing, you just be daid. So 'Be' be somewhere between where you be and where you ain't be, dat is, when you be daid. Any time you say 'Be' you is also saying 'ain't-Be', and dat make you think about being daid."

LOL. Having read Heidegger, I can appreciate this. Thanks for the link to the Strauss article. I'll check it out.
4 posted on 12/20/2003 1:35:21 PM PST by bdeaner
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 2 | View Replies]

To: bdeaner
In college, I only read the Stranger.

When I was a doctor, however, I read The Plague, and found it clinically interesting. In some way the plot is similar to the movie "jaws": a danger to the community occurs, and many refuse to recognize it, and many others feel there is nothing they can do to fight to danger, but a few people got together and decided to fight...even though the powerful in the town ridiculed their efforts, ... and because they chose to fight, the "plague" was defeated...

Then I saw a film on a French town that sheltered Jews...camus lived nearby to write this book...and it showed the allegory of the plague as nazism...and it is the story of how most French refused to recognize the horror of what was being done by the Nazis. But the small French village did, and sheltered hundreds of Jews, not "heroically" but merely saying, well they had to be sheltered, so we took them in"

A similar argument could be made about Islamofascism, that since we recognize it as a threat, we must fight...
5 posted on 12/20/2003 1:36:05 PM PST by LadyDoc (liberals only love politically correct poor people)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: Cicero
One must remember that all of this was written before modern refrigeration and ice cream.
6 posted on 12/20/2003 1:42:15 PM PST by Old Professer
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 2 | View Replies]

To: LadyDoc
A similar argument could be made about Islamofascism, that since we recognize it as a threat, we must fight...

Yes, exactly. The Plague is quite a good allegory for the situation we are in re: Islamism.

By the way, Doc, what's your specialty, or are you a general practitioner? I'm a clinical psychologist myself.
7 posted on 12/20/2003 1:51:08 PM PST by bdeaner
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 5 | View Replies]

To: Cicero
This thread is about Camus.

Belittling the understanding of mortality is near to playing the most dangerous game.
8 posted on 12/20/2003 1:52:47 PM PST by cornelis
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 2 | View Replies]

To: Cicero
Very interesting expostion on your part.

Off the mark somewhat, but maybe not really (Heidegger rubbing off, I guess?) is the following misconception:

They could experience a Nietzschean "vitality" that only intellectual Ubermensches of revolutionary culture like themselves could truly appreciate. And through the struggle for revolution, they could transcend the empty nothingness of everyday bourgeois existence that so upset them.

I was always under the impression that Nietzche's main philosophical thrust was that the mob (those inately or willingly ordinary), jealous of the superior man (inately or willfully extroadinary), and wanting to disable and destroy him, forms the 'collective' and by this means accomplishes the task.

Communism's goal is not to elevate the superior qualities in the superior man, but instead to lay low those superior beings, and raise up ordinary man, via the collective; the mob. That was part of the Soviet rationale when making the determimation that the bus driver should earn at least as much, if not more, than the physician. So I don't get how this author draws the Nietzchean analogy he does.

I like Nietzche, and consider him near an arch-Conservative, despite his animosity towards the religious in life. I attribute that to the probable cause of an overbearing, not-upright-enough to walk the walk, preacher-father.

But this piece does make me want to give Camus a shot.

9 posted on 12/20/2003 1:54:33 PM PST by AlbionGirl (A kite flies highest against the wind, not with it. - Winston Churchill)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 2 | View Replies]

To: LadyDoc
In a similar, but more popular than philosophical vein is De Hartog. In the 60s he wrote The Hospital, about the state of hospitals in Houston.
10 posted on 12/20/2003 1:56:44 PM PST by cornelis
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 5 | View Replies]

To: AlbionGirl
the mob (those inately or willingly ordinary), jealous of the superior man (inately or willfully extroadinary), and wanting to disable and destroy him, forms the 'collective' and by this means accomplishes the task.

Michael Oakeshott has an excellent essay on the rise of anti-individualism in the sixteenth century, "The masses in representative democracy."

11 posted on 12/20/2003 2:01:54 PM PST by cornelis
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 9 | View Replies]

To: cornelis
Sounds like similar themes as those in Ortega y Gasset's Revolt of the Masses and in Benda's Treason of the Intellectuals.
12 posted on 12/20/2003 2:12:00 PM PST by mrfixit514
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 11 | View Replies]

To: bdeaner
If I may be so modest, I have taught Camus' works for many years. As a moralist, Camus believed through goodness, happiness, liberty, justice, and brotherhood we could put meaning in our lives, moment to moment. (I am always amazed at the insistence of liberal academia to label him an existentialist, an epithet that even Camus rejected.)

A courageous man he was in so many ways, yes, but a conservative man as we know the term today, yes and no. The death penalty, for example, was an abhorent idea to him. Yet, he was ultra conservative in the sense that he fervently believed that governments should never interfere with human liberty, i.e., the ability of human beings to make their own choices and thus their own fate.

Well, I didn't plan on responding because I'm shutting down my computer now, but I was compelled to add to your statement.

With best wishes,

Penny


13 posted on 12/20/2003 2:28:30 PM PST by Penny
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: cornelis
I was born in Italy and emigrated to the States when I was just a little girl, and have been back to Italy many times. The reason I mention this, is that I noticed very early on that the peasant class, from which my lineage is derived, exhibits nearly all the tendencies attributed to them by Nietzche. And the most over-arching tendency being jealousy.

I'll give you an example: the last time I was there (2000) I met an old friend of the family, and he was doing very well financially. He's about my parents age of 70, and had done quite well for himself during the 60s and 70s, lost most of his wealth, and then climbed back out of that financial abyss.

I commented to some neighbors that Enzo was doing very well, and that his comeback was impressive. Their reply to me was, 'well maybe, but he's a little deaf, didn't you notice?' I didn't reply, except to shurg my shoulders in an attempt to relay the maxim that to argue against such entrenched obtuseness was obtuse in itself.

Anyway, my point is that rather than admit that he had indeed availed himself of some of his superior qualities, they had to find some unrelated defect, even if it meant naming something that was beyond his control.

The tendency of the inferior to do that is not confined to the peasants in Italy, or Europe in general. However, it flourishes there as opposed to here in the US, because here a man is judged and mostly admired (even if begrudgingly so) for his accomplishments.

That's the beauty of the US; a free society producing free minds. The greatest gift of my life, following the drawing of life's breath, was the gift of emigration to the United States.

14 posted on 12/20/2003 2:29:42 PM PST by AlbionGirl (A kite flies highest against the wind, not with it. - Winston Churchill)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 11 | View Replies]

To: AlbionGirl
So I don't get how this author draws the Nietzchean analogy he does.

The Nietzsche and Camus connection seems to be in the common theme of an emphasis upon life and vitality rather than death and that which is anathema to the vital. Nietzsche's beef with religion was only that it emphasized death at the expense of life, and raised weakness above power. Likewise, Camus was quick to point out that one must imagine Sisyphus happy.

On a similar note, I think it is important to distinguish between the "masses" and communitas. The masses represent the unthinking, mob-like mentality of those who attack greatness out of envy, and who appease their own feelings of weakness by identifying with an anonymous collective. The community, on the other hand, is formed by that vital bond between those who gather together to affirm and strengthen the good life.

Does this ring true with your reading of Nietzsche?
15 posted on 12/20/2003 2:30:44 PM PST by bdeaner
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 9 | View Replies]

To: Penny
Yet, he was ultra conservative in the sense that he fervently believed that governments should never interfere with human liberty, i.e., the ability of human beings to make their own choices and thus their own fate.

Thank you, Penny, for your analysis. It rings true to Camus for me. Incidently, I agree with Camus on the death penalty. I believe in the death penalty in an ideal world, in a just world -- but in a world where we can't even trust the judiciary with our Constitution, how can we trust it with our lives?
16 posted on 12/20/2003 2:35:46 PM PST by bdeaner
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 13 | View Replies]

To: bdeaner
Yes, it does for the most part.

However, when reading Nietzche though I did get the sense that communitas worked only on a very small scale, probably like the Kabutz (sp?) in Israel. But, that as the community expanded, as it was wont to do, the vissitudes of life were capable of transmogrifying it to the 'mob' pretty readily.

17 posted on 12/20/2003 2:37:56 PM PST by AlbionGirl (A kite flies highest against the wind, not with it. - Winston Churchill)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 15 | View Replies]

To: bdeaner
If you haven't already, you would enjoy reading "The Guest," a short story from his Exile in the Kingdom. The main character, Daru, mirrors nearly all of Camus' philosophical beliefs (and you'll note some existential touches in the landscape and in themes of alienation as well). A search on Google will yield it for you. (Who knows? You may even arrive on one of my college web site pages).

I understand even though I do not share completely your views on the death penalty. Another time, perhaps, we can discuss this issue on this forum.

Best to you again,
Penny

18 posted on 12/20/2003 2:49:51 PM PST by Penny
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 16 | View Replies]

To: AlbionGirl
Interesting story. It's good to have freedom, and more importantly, the freedom to know what is right and the freedom to do right.

The author mentions the chief distinction between nihilism and Camus: good and evil. But there may be another distinction which the consideration of death brings to light and even abhorrent "existentialism" points out: the meaning of good and evil is contingent on the meaning of death. In Marxism, which runs on class envy, the orientation of freedom and humanity is immanent, which means that the social order is for this world and this world alone, not after death. Death is easy come easy go, with trains and chambers etc.

Some pragmatic views in the United States still allow the consideration of the "future" to capture the meaning of justice, but more and more this is falling away in proportion to which death has become meaningless except for a good joke.

19 posted on 12/20/2003 3:00:21 PM PST by cornelis
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 14 | View Replies]

To: Penny
I am always amazed at the insistence of liberal academia to label him an existentialist, an epithet that even Camus rejected.

I know. It's because most of them have only read The Myth of Sisyphus or more likely the CliffNotes version. That one is an express rejection of Heidegger's nothingness - it's what existentialism might have become had not Sartre turned it into an exercise in self-dramatizing and navel-gazing.

The Plague really is a good novel, but it was intended to speak to contemporaries for whom the historical allusions were more obvious then they are in an age when students can't reliably recite who fought World War II. Sartre and Roland Barthes have, in fact, stated that the book is weakened because it lacks direct historical allusion, which I have always suspected was, in fact, a refusal to see it as a mirror for their own activities. In fact, it does not, and its setting, Oran, is not accidental either - French, and yet not France, the characters Camus's contemporaries, and yet not his contemporaries. (I've always suspected it's as close as he felt he could get without a libel suit.)

I don't think it was an allegory at all, although it certainly was heavily metaphorical and broadly allusive to the experience of growing Nazism in his native land. The principal issue for the protagonist is to what degree the impending social catastrophe impels him as a reclusive, reflective individual, to embark on direct action in opposition. It is both a measuring of what individual and collective actually owe one another and what degree that individual may remain withdrawn and still be true to his ethical beliefs with respect to that relation. That is a direct and unflinching statement of the difficulties Nazism represented to the French philosophes of the mid-twentieth century, which Camus answered by joining the resistance early and Sartre, very late. It is little wonder that the latter does not want to see himself in The Plague.

20 posted on 12/20/2003 3:07:03 PM PST by Billthedrill
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 13 | View Replies]


Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first 1-2021-4041-6061-80 next last

Disclaimer: Opinions posted on Free Republic are those of the individual posters and do not necessarily represent the opinion of Free Republic or its management. All materials posted herein are protected by copyright law and the exemption for fair use of copyrighted works.

Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

FreeRepublic, LLC, PO BOX 9771, FRESNO, CA 93794
FreeRepublic.com is powered by software copyright 2000-2008 John Robinson