Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

Skip to comments.

Berkeley s Radical An Interview with Phillip E. Johnson
Touchstone Magazine ^ | June 2002 | Touchstone interview

Posted on 05/29/2002 8:32:25 AM PDT by cornelis

Touchstone Magazine Home

Berkeley’s Radical

An Interview with Phillip E. Johnson

 

Phillip E. Johnson, J.D. (University of Chicago), is Professor of Law (emeritus) at the University of California at Berkeley, where he taught for 30 years. A frequent lecturer, he is also the author of Darwin on Trial, Reason in the Balance, Defeating Darwinism by Opening Minds, and The Wedge of Truth (all InterVarsity), as well as of two textbooks on criminal law.

Dr. Johnson is an elder in the Presbyterian Church (U.S.A.), and he now has a regular column in Touchstone, "The Leading Edge." James M. Kushiner interviewed Johnson while attending a conference on Intelligent Design at Yale University in November 2000.

 

Touchstone: Dr. Johnson, tell us about your upbringing. Were you raised in a Christian home?

Phillip Johnson (PJ): Well, I grew up in Aurora, Illinois. We went to Sunday school because it was good for us kids. We’d drop my dad off at the golf course on the way. My mother told me I had to stay until I got confirmed, then I could go my own way. During high school I went to a liberal Congregationalist church, but I never took Christian doctrine seriously. It was just part of the culture, like the Boy Scouts. It was about being nice.

I went to Harvard at 17 and assumed I was leaving all that behind. I had every intention of simply adopting the Harvard philosophy, which was secular, pragmatic, and rational, because that’s what you did if you wanted to be a big deal.

When did you go to Harvard?

PJ: In 1957, which was a significant year, the year of Sputnik. Sputnik created a completely new situation in American higher education because it scared the government; they thought we were going to lose our scientific preeminence. So they poured an enormous amount of money into the universities, especially for science. That’s when the biological sciences
curriculum really got started.

When you were at Harvard, were you on the "left" or the "right"?

PJ: I played at being the leftist, but I came from a conservative Midwestern background, so my instincts were always in that direction. I was just trying out my wings.

But when I got to the University of Chicago Law School, I discovered that all the bright people weren’t liberals. I heard about Milton Friedman and George Stigler and other leading American economists whom I was never told about at Harvard. It was a bit of an eye-opener.

But unlike many people who go to Chicago, I didn’t quite "eat the whole enchilada," which allowed me to be more flexible. I didn’t completely buy into the market ideology, though I respected it.

I did well in law school, which put me in line to get top judicial clerkships, and then eventually became a professor. One of the biggest decisions I made in my life was choosing Berkeley instead of Yale. When I was a Supreme Court clerk, I was eagerly recruited by both, but I decided I’d rather live in Berkeley. The Berkeley law professors were more like me—public-school types. The Yale professors were a little too preppy for me. I thought, "Well, I’ll never be a member of the club there," so I went to Berkeley.

I was a perfectly ordinary, middle-of-the-road secular rationalist, and a half-educated intellectual. I did well on tests but never worked very hard at my studies. I look back now and see that I didn’t really know very much. I probably was a pretty ignorant person.

When did you go to Berkeley?

PJ: I started teaching law at Berkeley in 1967. In the 1970s they had even more student unrest at Harvard and Yale than at Berkeley. After I was at Berkeley and saw the student revolution up close, I found it wasn’t very interesting. The leftist riots were old hat, and I got fed up with the irrational self-righteousness. This experience, which would have been the same at Yale, pushed me into a much more conservative set of views.

How did you come to realize the secular view lacked something? Obviously, one of the most important decisions you made was to become a Christian. How did that happen?

PJ: I became disillusioned during my thirties. The whole idea of the exciting campus ferment and student ideas became a disappointment. The academic career was also a disappointment. I think my motives for going into it, for everything I did, were rather shallow. I was basically an academic careerist seeking tenure, writing law review articles and a casebook. I had the career, but I was bored with it. I thought life ought to be more fulfilling than that. I was beginning to grow up.

I had been very happily married for some years, and then my marriage went bad. My wife got a heavy dose of the ideas that were rolling around in the ’70s. She lost interest in our home and family and went off into artistic politics. After we split up, I took care of the kids. So I was disillusioned with my home life, my marriage, and my academic career.

In terms of my religious views during this period, what I usually say is, "I was raised as a nominal Christian and then I became a nominal agnostic." I didn’t have any passion for it. In fact, I had read some of C. S. Lewis’s books when I was in college and law school and admired them. I thought that they were attractive but not for people like me in modern times. "Too bad they aren’t true" was my reaction.

When my marriage ended, I wondered what I was going to do with the rest of my life. That’s when I had my conversion experience. This, I think, is true of many people; what leads you to a conversion is the loss of your faith in something else. My faith had been, "If you’re a bright person with the right credentials, you’ll have a happy and meaningful life." I expected that I would go from one distinguished position to the next, advance my career, be happy and satisfied, and that’s what life would be about. It seemed to me that wasn’t happening, and I was just going to be a law teacher for the rest of my life. It wasn’t very meaningful or as good as I thought it would be. So I lost faith during that pragmatic period. Instead, I thought, "What makes me think that what I have is better than the Christian life?"

So I became a Christian when I was 38 and met my present wife, Kathie, at the First Presbyterian Church of Berkeley. Our lives were centered in that church. Kathie had been raised in a nominal Methodist home, and her first husband, like my first wife, had been very anti-Christian. So you might say we were negatively evangelized by our first spouses.

My conversion was gradual, not dramatic. The central issue for me was whether Christianity was real or imaginary. I lived in a society at the university that mostly assumed an easy-going agnosticism. So I felt it was necessary to come to a conclusion on whether Christian metaphysics were real or imaginary, or if I would be throwing my brains out the window and adopting a myth because it satisfied my personal needs.

 

How did you resolve that question?

PJ: First, I took up jurisprudence, the philosophical roots of law. That was in the wake of the emergence of what we call the Critical Legal Studies movement, which was the postmodernist, deconstructionist, epistemological relativism and Marxism that were in the English departments and had just come into the law schools, especially at Harvard and Stanford. I found it quite interesting. I was asked by the Stanford Law Review to contribute a negative piece to a volume of articles by leading members of the movement because they wanted an outsider’s view.

I spent a whole year on that, reading these dense 120-page law review articles, studying continental
philosophy, and so on, and developed a love-hate relationship with neo-Marxism. I disliked the infantile leftist politics intensely. I did agree with their critique of liberal rationalism and legal scholarship—where the law professor and the judge say, "Well, you there, you have your passions and your prejudices and your interests, whereas I just peer into the Constitution and decide what justice is." It’s what I called the sham neutrality of liberal rationalism.

One of the leading examples of that was in the section on religion. In my article—my study guide of sham neutrality—I used as my textbook example the decision of the California Supreme Court on the government funding of abortions. The US Supreme Court said, "You have the right to get an abortion, but it’s not
unconstitutional for Congress to refuse to fund abortions as part of medical care." However, the California Supreme Court decided the issue the other way around; they said, "You do have to fund it." The justification for that conclusion began, "Now, we’re not saying anything about the morality of abortion, we simply don’t take any stance on that. All we’re saying is that abortion has to be treated like other forms of child-birth decisions." So I said, "Well, why don’t you say, ‘We’re not saying anything about the morality of abortion, we just feel it has to be treated as the equivalent of other forms of homicide?’" The classification was a moral statement, so it was a sham neutrality.

I used to refer jokingly to myself as the entire right wing of the Critical Legal Studies movement, which in their view was a contradiction in terms. Their critique was purely the instrument of a left-wing political program, which was chosen arbitrarily and presumed to be good. It was a faith commitment.

I picked up the same critique these Marxist law professors were making and turned it against a different set of subjects. My aim always was to demystify the kinds of doctrines the Critical Legal scholars wanted to protect. It never would have occurred to any of them to apply this sort of critique to a case promoting abortion because in their book that was a good thing. So it occurred to me, "Well, this can just as well be used to a different purpose. Let’s deconstruct Marx." So that got me into jurisprudence and prompted a skeptical attitude towards rationalism.

I see the fruit of that now, 20 years later, in the first chapter of The Wedge of Truth. The young man I wrote about, Philip Wentworth, goes to Harvard, where he learns to keep an "open mind," but all that’s really happened is that he’s gone with the fashionable crowd and adopted their fashion, as he meant to do from the start. (I recognize so much of myself in that story.)

I became acutely aware that what we think is reasoning is very often rationalization. When you speak of rationality, there are two very distinct components. One is logical reasoning, which is about going from premises to conclusions, conclusions that should be as good as your premises. Thus, logic will get you into insanity if you’ve got the wrong premises.

The other component of rationality is having the right premises. How do you get them and how do you determine that they are right? Not by logical reasoning, surely, because then you would be reasoning from other premises in order to justify them. There is an instinct, or revelation, or whatever you want to call it, that underlies your thinking, and the only interesting problem in philosophy is how you get that.

After figuring that out, it was the death of rationalism, as far as I was concerned. The problem with rationalism is that it isn’t rational. It fails to give sufficient importance to the development of the choice of the right premises; it tries to justify them by circular reasoning. Once I was alert to that distinction, I was able to critique the things that previously I felt I had to take for granted.

Such as?

PJ: Eventually, the theory of evolution. Remember that my interest was in finding out whether the Christian gospel was rational. Of course, it wasn’t rational by the standards of the academic world. One of the good things about the Christian life was that it opened up a whole world of intellectual input that previously had been closed to me. I began to understand what was actually wrong with the academic culture, and to put a name on my uneasiness. It was the seed of what would later be a full-blown critique of Darwinism. It "evolved" in a directed and purposeful manner!

I am now primarily dealing with people who have incorporated naturalist metaphysics into their definitions of science and reason. I’ve learned to identify that tendency, and I understand it very empathetically because I lived there for so long. I’m very different from most of the people I associate with now because they grew up in a Christian subculture, whereas my roots are in the academic subculture. I have a different set of experiences and thoughts.

"Where do the givens come from?" was the question I often asked myself. Eventually, that led me to the whole question of the gospel, and the way Jesus deals with people. "Follow me," he said. He gave a new set of premises, a new foundation. One of the very interesting things about Jesus is that when he deals with people, whether they are believers or unbelievers, friends or foes, they are supposed to know who he is. It’s perfectly understandable: "I am who I say I am." When you see the truth, when you meet it face to face, you’re expected to know it. If you refuse it, you are refusing to see the truth. I found that very fascinating—"How can that be?"

Much later I discovered Lesslie Newbigin, which was like meeting a long-lost twin brother from whom I had been separated at birth. We’d had totally different lives—he was an older man and a missionary—but I recognized in what he was writing the same line of thought that I had independently stumbled upon. Either the gospel of Christ is the centerpiece of a new order or it’s nothing. That was so fascinating to me. Then I saw how this was the right principle and starting point. In all of my writing, I concentrate on that starting point. "In the beginning was the Word." A few simple principles. If you stay with those, you’ll be all right.

When you say "the givens," do you mean the revelation that we have in Scripture, or is it something larger than that?

PJ: Something larger. The gospel is not the writing. It’s described in the writing, but the Book of Mark isn’t "the Way, the Truth, and the Life"—Jesus is. It’s apparent in the Christian gospel that he is a living presence with whom you can make contact today. I sometimes say, when speaking in Christian circles, that I’m convinced that Jesus was who he said he was and did what he set out to do, but I’m not always sure that Christianity is a good thing. People erect the structures, which are partly divine in origin and incorporate part of the truth, but they also manufacture part of it and bring cultural influences to it.

Do you see anything of value in pre-Christian philosophical thinking?

PJ: If you read the Socratic dialogues and some of the things Socrates said, it’s really eerie. Socrates says extraordinary things like, "If the perfect man ever lived on earth, you know what they’d do to him? They’d crucify him." Where did that come from?

From insight?

PJ: Yes. It’s the most profound kind of insight at times. The critique of the common understanding of justice, the conspiracy of the weak against the strong in Book Two of The Republic, is something I review every year in my classes. It’s the most profound analysis of human nature that you can get. On the other hand, there are a lot of dregs in Greek philosophy, too, so I wouldn’t swallow it whole.

Humanly speaking, you have to understand all of their ideas in the light of tradition. Nobody should try to think entirely for himself; you learn an enormous amount from what has gone before. That there were other early important Christian thinkers was news to me. I didn’t know whom I was reading about when I first encountered the Fathers of the Church because the version of Christianity I knew goes from St. Paul to Augustine to Aquinas and then to Calvin and Luther. So I think it’s just wonderful that many Christians are rediscovering the church fathers.

So as a Christian you moved from philosophical considerations to an attack on Darwinism. Why Darwinism?

PJ: I wanted to know whether the fundamentals of the Christian worldview were fact or fantasy. Darwinism is a logical place to begin because, if Darwinism is true, Christian metaphysics is fantasy. That’s why it’s so marginalized and is considered to be of no intellectual interest.

I was surprised last night when someone quoted Darwin as saying, "Well, if we’re going to talk about such-and-such, then you may as well ask about the origins of life." Darwin seemed to be putting the origin of life into a separate category of questions he wasn’t really addressing.

PJ: Darwin was unsure about the origins of life, but he also made the initial speculation about life evolving
in a warm little pond. The whole Darwinist method was immediately extended to include the origin of life. Darwinism is the methodology of philosophical materialism. Maybe physicalism would be a better term, given that Darwin didn’t develop every last inch of the philosophy.

I got the opportunity when I was on a sabbatical in London in 1987 or 1988 to read more about Darwinism. It was immensely interesting to discover that it’s all circular reasoning, deception, and pseudo-science. I had suspected that, but I saw that it was really true. It is a pseudo-science that simply works for confirming examples of a materialist philosophical system that’s held up by a priori grids.

Was there anything you read that "made the light go on," so to speak?

PJ: The first book I read while on sabbatical was Dawkins’s Blind Watchmaker, which seemed fairly convincing on the first reading but full of holes on the second. Michael Denton’s Evolution: A Theory in Crisis did much to alert me to the issues.

But perhaps the greatest "Aha!" moment came when I was browsing in a bookstore in London with my wife. Kathie had been a bit skeptical of my developing interest in evolution. (I sometimes get in a little over my head.) She picked up a copy of Isaac Asimov’s Guide to Science—900 pages of pretty good popular science writing—looked up evolution, and there was a brief description of the theory, plus three pages of heavy-handed ad hominem denunciation of creationists for not accepting the absolute truth of this theory that was so obvious to all thinking persons. Then there was a brief section called "Proof of Evolution," in which the entire proof—all the proof that Asimov thought was necessary—was the peppered moth experiment. So Kathie thought about it and said to me, "I think you’re on to something." Such experiences have been repeated many times.

The ignorance that’s involved, the indifference to the facts, is stunning. Anything that promotes the "Great Darwin" and the materialist understanding is uncritically received, unless it does something that’s politically incorrect.

In short, my discovery that the reasoning in Darwinism is unscientific, illogical, and dishonest was tremendously important to me because it validates that "In the beginning was the Word" is really the correct starting point.

I then got to know the people from the main-stream community and the creationist world who are critical of Darwinism. What I brought to the dissident movement—Nancy Pearcey has pointed this out—was a sense of strategy.

People were caught in a rationalist mentality. They were thinking, "If we present facts and evidence, Stephen J. Gould will say, ‘Oh yes, you’re right and I’m wrong,’" and then the scientists would let them in. Well, I understand a little bit better how that world works, and I thought of it like a political campaign or big case litigation.

So the question is: "How to win?" That’s when I began to develop what you now see full-fledged in the "wedge" strategy: "Stick with the most important thing"—the mechanism and the building up of information. Get the Bible and the Book of Genesis out of the debate because you do not want to raise the so-called Bible-science dichotomy. Phrase the argument in such a way that you can get it heard in the secular academy and in a way that tends to unify the religious dissenters. That means concentrating on, "Do you need a Creator to do the creating, or can nature do it on its own?" and refusing to get sidetracked onto other issues, which people are always trying to do. They’ll ask, "What do you think of Noah’s flood?" or something like that. Never bite on such questions because they’ll lead you into a trackless wasteland and you’ll never get out of it.

How did others become involved in the "wedge" strategy?

PJ: I met Steve Meyer, who was in England at the time. Through Steve, I got to know the others, who were developing what became the Intelligent Design movement. Michael Denton stayed in my home for three days while he was in the United States. Meyer introduced me to Paul Nelson, and so on. One by one, these people came together.

At that time there was a little funding to pay for people to come to Seattle occasionally for a conference. So they had me speak at one in 1989 to look me over. I soon became the leader of the group.

I also was introduced to Stephen Jay Gould and his scientific people and attended a seminar in the Boston area where I debated him, which gave me more confidence in our work. That was before I published Darwin on Trial. Of course, I’m much more knowledgeable now than I was then, but even then I still could hold my own with the kingpin on the other side. The debate was a draw, which was all I needed because a draw was as good as a victory.

Indeed, my philosophy is, when I do a serious debate, to play for a draw because I do not want my opponent and the audience going away saying, "That is one clever lawyer who can make you look like a fool in a debate." I want them to go away saying, "There’s more to this than I thought. We ought to do this again." All you have to do is get the right issues on the table and then you win. You don’t have to worry about it, because Darwinism is wrong, and it will self-destruct.

By the time Darwin on Trial was published, I had pretty well worked out the strategy I thought would, in time, win this campaign, and I’ve been able to convince most of the young-earth creationists and the old-earth creationists that this is the right way to proceed.

I had thought that I would be able to persuade the theistic evolutionists, but that was a total failure. It wasn’t until I got to know them that I learned how they think. They are guided by the principle that we’re not supposed to have any disagreements with the scientific establishment over science. Everything Richard Dawkins says is perfectly right and acceptable up to the moment he says, "And therefore there is no God." If he just didn’t say those last words, he would be fine. I discovered that there was a total lack of interest in evidence and in asking scientific questions. When I tried to tell them it wasn’t just the "And therefore there is no God" sentence that expressed Dawkins’s atheism, but his whole scientific explanation was grounded in it, they were very resentful that I even raised the objection.

So they see a great gulf fixed between science and personal faith?

PJ: Yes. For them, the enemy is the Christian fundamentalist.

Well, aren’t you their enemy, too?

PJ: When people start bashing fundamentalists, they start out talking about extreme literalists and so on. But the definition is in fact much broader than that. Anybody who thinks God is real in the sense that evolution is real is a fundamentalist. God is a Sunday morning truth or a Bible-study group truth. That’s the way the secular world has it. They’re willing to tolerate Christian faith among the students and faculty, provided they don’t bring it into the classroom and the work world, where we talk about what really happened.

Theistic evolutionists are very content with maintaining that arrangement. They think that they could get along well with the secular world if it weren’t for those troublemaking fundamentalists—and everybody who makes trouble is a fundamentalist.

I was the biggest troublemaker of all, so I found myself bitterly resented in the Christian academic world. Theistic evolution is the same thing as atheistic evolution with a certain amount of God-talk. They don’t see any merit whatsoever in alleging that God left us some fingerprints on the evidence.

I should add that some of my close allies, colleagues, and friends are Christian college professors, so it’s not as if they’re all that way.

So theistic evolutionists aren’t open to discussing Intelligent Design?

PJ: We’ve tried many times, but I’ve found that they are even harder to reason with than the atheistic evolutionists. I’ve been able to get along with the atheistic evolutionists better. It’s disappointing.

But aside from that, I would now say that the project of developing a central position, which could unify the Christian world on this issue, has been accomplished. We’re on the verge of success in the project of legitimating this issue in the secular academic realm. I don’t know exactly when to say we’ve been successful. Maybe when we get a serious article about us in Time or the New York Times. We’re still on the margins. We have this conference at Yale, but the Yale faculty aren’t really embracing it. We had the conference at Baylor and got very eminent people from the other side to attend, so we’re close to success on that front, but we haven’t reached it. We have reached success in the unification of people who disagree about a whole lot of other things but agree that the wedge strategy is correct.

Are you happy with the broadness of the coalition in the sense of including Catholics and Orthodox?

PJ: Very happy. I think Catholic support is very important. A lot of Orthodox are friendly to it, and I also consider the Orthodox to be major players in this. I greatly cherish their support. Our movement is by its very nature ecumenical. One of the reasons why this issue has always been a loser is that it’s only been taken up by Protestant fundamentalists. That has to change.

It’s like the stereotype of the Scopes trial all over again.

PJ: That’s a large reason for my redefining the issue. The mechanism of the wedge strategy is to make it attractive to Catholics, Orthodox, non-fundamentalist Protestants, observant Jews, and so on. This will be a long fight. Every month we’re moving ahead, even when we get a little bit of a setback.

Once you absorb yourself in the issues and understand the way Darwinians think, you know that it’s wrong and it’s vulnerable, which is why they fight so desperately to maintain their monopoly on the public forum.

You have said there is no natural explanation for the rise of genetic information. How important is that question in the debate?

PJ: The Wedge of Truth is all about those issues. The scientific key is, "No natural processes create genetic information." As soon as we get that out, there’s only one way the debate can go because Darwinists aren’t going to come up with a mechanism. They’ll start out talking about the peppered moth, and when that self-destructs, then they’ll say, "Oh, self-organizing systems, or the fourth law of thermodynamics," and other nonsense, which is just covering up ignorance.

Genetic information is the issue, but it isn’t the final issue. After you make that breakthrough, then you see other ways in which the theory is questionable. Darwinists will say, "Oh, well, maybe the mechanism has some problems, but the "fact of evolution"—common ancestry—is not in question. We distinguish the fact of evolution from the mechanism of evolution."

But that’s a bogus distinction because the "fact"—common ancestry—incorporates the mechanism. It’s just a matter of "now you see it, now you don’t." They are saying the mechanism by which a father and mother give birth to children is the same mechanism by which our "bacterial ancestors" gave birth to human beings. They say it’s all a process of natural reproduction and naturally occurring variation in the offspring.

Biologists affiliated with the Intelligent Design movement nail down the distinction by showing that DNA mutations do not create evolution in any significant sense. Instead, they make birth defects, so the whole thing is false from the get-go. There is no way you can establish that a bacterium is the parent of a complex animal. There is no mechanism to make the change, no historical or fossil evidence that such a change ever occurred, and there’s no way to duplicate the process in a lab.

Once you get that in the debate, then we will be poised for a metaphysical and intellectual reversal that is every bit as profound as the one with Copernicus. People will say, "My gosh, we’ve been completely misled by this fundamental truth of the creation story of our culture. We can no longer understand the world that way."

How do you change the way people regard the authority of science? Get them to think of it as a much more limited thing. Science is very reliable when scientists stick to the kinds of things that can be tested by refutable experiments, but much of what they tell us is outside that. When they have to fake the mechanisms, it becomes a very dubious philosophy. That raises the question of why so many very brilliant people were misled for so long and did such a good job of rationalizing these things.

When the mechanism of Darwinism becomes discredited, it’s like a train that’s been turned around. You can say, "Well, that’s interesting, but the train is still in the same place. The world, Yale, Berkeley, are still there. The New York Times is still telling us what to think. So why isn’t everything different?" Well, it is different, but you can’t see it yet. The train is turned in the opposite direction. It’s going to start out very slowly, but it’s moving on the logical tracks towards something very different, and when we get there, our great-great-grand-children will see how different things are.

What are some of the books and writers that were formative influences on you?

PJ: I’ve told you I had read the popular Christian classics of Lewis and Chesterton and later, Lesslie Newbigin, and admired them. Michael Denton first introduced me to the fundamentals of the skeptical case about Darwinism.

When I think about things, much of what I get comes from my amateur’s interest in history, especially military history. I’m always thinking things like, "This is like Napoleon in Moscow. He’s taken over the whole country, but he’s about to lose his army." The sweep of historical examples, rather than the philosophers, has influenced me.

I’m a great admirer of the literary classics by Chaucer, Shakespeare, Milton, and the Victorian novelists, especially Austen and Trollope. These are writers who help you have a Christian mindset. I think one of the great tragedies is that the loss of Christian faith and the meaning it gives to people’s lives makes it impossible for them to really appreciate literature. With a play like Hamlet, for example, you have to inhabit the Christian metaphysical rooms to really grasp what the ghost is and understand that marvelous scene in which Hamlet decides not to kill the king while he is saying his prayers.

Those are the formative influences: history and literary classics. I also give a lot of credit to the authors I fought against.

Who are your heroes?

PJ: C. S. Lewis certainly was an intellectual hero in that Oxford common-room atmosphere of his time, to stand up for what he believed was right. The other reason I find him so overwhelmingly admirable is that when he was discouraged about philosophical issues after he debated Elisabeth Anscombe, he went off and wrote the Narnia Chronicles. How could a man like that, with no experience with children, write enduring classics of children’s literature? It’s one of the most astounding feats of virtuosity in literary history.

My wife is a collector of children’s literature—we have 25,000 volumes in our home—so I have a deep appreciation for it, and for the ability to communicate with young people. Many people are urging me to try my hand at that sort of thing but I’ve never gotten up the nerve. Maybe I will someday.

What’s next for Phil Johnson?

PJ: I’m phasing out my direct involvement in the battle over evolution because the next generation is perfectly capable of carrying the ball. Jonathan Wells, Steve Meyer, Mike Behe, and the rest know more than I do and are very capable writers and debaters.

My next project is to provide excellent worldview education for high school and college students. I see this as a fantastic opportunity to send thousands of these young people properly prepared into the best universities and graduate schools, with a mission to speak the truth and change them by prophetic utterance. I love the sense of having opened a young person’s mind to truth and reality and knowing that they can do a great work. Nothing is more satisfying than that. If they have a better idea, they will be successful over time in changing the world. That’s what I want to be directly involved in.

My colleague John Mark Reynolds and I are working with donors and organizations to design educational programs. We are proud of the Torrey Honors Institute at Biola University. The young people who are here at this conference are so eager to be intellectually empowered and capable of taking on these issues. I think we can teach them how to do that. They will be better educated than the students at secular schools.

I see my work as not just being about a scientific theory—it’s about the definitions of knowledge and reality. I see it as empowering this young generation, and I also see it as being inherently ecumenical. That’s represented by John Mark being Eastern Orthodox and me being a Presbyterian elder. Wherever I go, whether to a Southern Baptist, Catholic, or Orthodox church, I feel accepted into the Body.

The first thousand years of the Christian faith was the era of the great councils and of unity in the faith. The second millennium was the millennium of the schisms—the great East-West schism, the Reformation, and the splintering of Protestantism—and then the near destruction of the whole thing in the wake of materialism in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. But I see that ground being recaptured. All those centuries of strife and conflict and hatred—the engine has run down. There are still people who want to keep it going—I’ve met some of them—but I think the overwhelming sense is that we’re tired of that. The third millennium has to be the millennium of reconstitution—from the bottom up. It’s about recapturing the sense of the mystical union of the Body of Christ at the grassroots level. I see that happening all the time.  

The Right Questions: Truth, Meaning, and Public Debate by Phillip E. Johnson is due out in September 2002 from InterVarsity Press.

 

 

Copyright © 2002 the Fellowship of St. James. All rights reserved.



Home -
Online Store - Archives - Speakers & Conferences - Contact Us



TOPICS: Culture/Society; Philosophy
KEYWORDS: crevolist
Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first previous 1-20 ... 501-520521-540541-560561-577 next last
To: tortoise
Well, Tortoise - as this is not my specialty, I have trouble following all of the verbiage. If you should be right in your assertion - that the human mind can be expressable by a universal Turing machine - I will be amazed. Again, time will tell who is right.
521 posted on 06/03/2002 1:20:55 PM PDT by yendu bwam
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 520 | View Replies]

To: tortoise
...there is a bit of excitement in many circles that the first general AI technology is imminent...

Thanks for your interesting post. Are you saying that formulas have recently been developed implementing Hofstadter's "strange loops" theory?

As recently as last year, in a new forward to GEB, he was complaining that his theory of consciousness and AI was not being taken seriously enough in the field.

522 posted on 06/03/2002 2:05:24 PM PDT by beckett
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 458 | View Replies]

To: yendu bwam
Well, Tortoise - as this is not my specialty, I have trouble following all of the verbiage. If you should be right in your assertion - that the human mind can be expressable by a universal Turing machine - I will be amazed. Again, time will tell who is right.

The ultimate question boils down to whether or not the human mind is running on finite state machinery. If it is, then real AI must be possible in silicon. If it isn't, then it isn't possible on conventional machinery. There is a mathematical way to test "black boxed" machinery for "finite state-ness", which while not proof in a mathematically rigorous sense, can make a determination one way or the other with an extremely high statistical confidence. All such tests applied to the human mind that I am aware of indicate that the human mind is in fact a piece of complex finite state machinery to a high degree of statistical confidence.

Again, while this doesn't "prove" anything in a rigorous sense, few people are willing to bet against the extremely miniscule odds that the human mind isn't running on finite state machinery at this point. This doesn't speak as to the construction of the machinery, only its mathematical nature. So there is a theoretical chance you could be correct, but I wouldn't bet on it. As you said, time will tell.

523 posted on 06/03/2002 2:12:31 PM PDT by tortoise
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 521 | View Replies]

To: tortoise
In a broader sense, the only thing we really know about the computational process of the human mind is that it is finite state machinery (this is something that can be measured and tested without knowing the mechanics of the machinery)

Finite in it’s inability to know/learn everything?
Knowledge for the each individual mind is limited by will power as much as any other factor

Or finite in a natural truth table/binary sense?
It would seem that even if the yes/no equations came from nature, our mind still has the free will to choose what the decision will be – even if it were not the logical or moral decision.

It seems in any case that AI is limited to ‘our’ knowledge. Still, how would we enable ‘true’ free will?
The only complete truth table comes from a complete knowledge base. This is not represented by mere numbers but formulas and equations. The formulas and equations are obeyed in nature but not necessarily in the human mind.

524 posted on 06/03/2002 2:40:48 PM PDT by Heartlander
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 520 | View Replies]

To: beckett
Thanks for your interesting post. Are you saying that formulas have recently been developed implementing Hofstadter's "strange loops" theory?

While I've never framed it like this, there is a close analog to Hostadter's Strange Loops implicit in the operation of this new class of state machinery that is being described. It is just one dimension however, and not the core principle (it would be difficult to construct useful computing machinery on that theory alone). Hofstadter's strange loops were not a goal in the mathematical derivation, but an analog emerges as a consequence of it.

While GEB is still very highly regarded in the AI community, it is considered more of a brilliant primer than an advanced text. Sadly, Hofstadter's later works fell short of his original. I still have fond memories of GEB, though I haven't read it in at least a decade.

525 posted on 06/03/2002 2:46:05 PM PDT by tortoise
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 522 | View Replies]

To: jennyp
Because how we deal with Truth is important. One side of this debate spends all its time either frantically waving away the facts or waving away the logical, reasonable implications of the facts. Our side embraces the facts, and reason is our friend. Don't be afraid of facts and logic.

I agree that Truth is very important, jennyp, but it has more than a material dimension. And thanks for the advice but I am not the least bit afraid of facts or logic which, I repeat, is precisely my problem with Evolution. All-in-all, however, and excepting the interpretive commentary, I would agree with the substance of your post. Glory be!

526 posted on 06/03/2002 7:39:30 PM PDT by Phaedrus
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 511 | View Replies]

To: tortoise
The design parameter for a species is reproductive fitness, an important part of which is survival. The design selection process in nature takes care of itself, though the rather loose selection parameters permit quite a bit of divergence.

Thanks.

Reproductive fitness and survival are both slippery concepts; i.e. the Evolutionists can tell us which species were fit and which were not but only after the fact, based on their "survival". They cannot tell us, now, which species exhibit reproductive fitness and will survive and which do not. So how much scientific meaning do such concepts have? Looking back, anyone can play Monday morning quarterback and impose patterns where they may or may not in fact exist.

I presume by "the design selection process in nature takes care of itself" you refer to environmental constraints, and those constraints are certainly real. But this is the passive aspect of Evolution on which all or most can agree.

Endless repetition to the contrary by the Evolutionists notwithstanding, and acknowledging the common amino acid bases, genetic similarities and the increasing complexity of forms over time, it has simply not been shown that any species can or does evolve into another. The evidence is simply not there, in the fossil record, in the lab, anywhere. So while Evolution has a nice, linear, cause-and-effect feel and tone, it simply isn't supported by the data.

Exploring possibilities a little, mutation has been posited as a change agent. But mutation is destructive and produces freaks, genetic information is lost, not gained. It's a dead end. Gould celebrated "chance" as at the bottom of things for a while but as a mathematician you know that such a position is utter scientific nonsense and laughable. At all events, species have a tendency to show great stability over long long periods of time, not change.

Well, you're getting the drift, I'm sure. The case has not been made so the best that can honestly and scientifically be said is "We don't know".

Now the Evolutionists are in denial about this and here the implications become quite interesting to me, but that is a whole nother realm, the realm of the Culture War.

527 posted on 06/03/2002 8:10:02 PM PDT by Phaedrus
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 512 | View Replies]

To: tortoise
Your discussion of AI is fascinating to the extent that I can follow it, which is not very far. Are you, or rather, is the field assuming that material brain is equivalent to mind? If so, my bet would be that the effort will not succeed in any significant way. As I say, though, I will always hew to the facts and evidence.
528 posted on 06/03/2002 8:27:45 PM PDT by Phaedrus
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 523 | View Replies]

To: PatrickHenry; jennyp; VadeRetro;
Were our species to evolve into something different -- which might occur if we settled various planetary systems and different populations were isolated for long (really long) periods -- I can't imagine a scenario where our current concepts of justice wouldn't be applicable to all the various offshoots of humanity.

Hello PatrickHenry! On the one hand, you say you think human nature is "relatively fixed." But then you say that different populations, if isolated long enough, might evolve into something different; i.e., into something with a different nature, I gather; but that you have doubts that such evolution would wind up with a termite-like species which, of course, involves a quite radically different type of nature than the human.

Then somehow you assume or infer (projecting your current stock of knowledge and state of awareness) that notions of justice and morality would be pretty much the same -- or at least the need of them, this gets kinda fuzzy here -- in all cases or at least most cases, with the possible exception of the termite scenario. But then you don't know anything about termite morality to go on, I gather; thus you do not further speculate.

Some thoughts. In order for ideas of justice and morality to arise, there must be as the ground condition self-aware and self-reflected consciousness. It is the nature of homo sapiens to possess this characteristic, distinguishing feature, though it is highly doubtful that the same may be said for termites.

So I guess it really would depend on what forms subsequent evolutions of human nature were to take before we could speculate about whether they would care about or need justice or morality, let alone what forms, if any, such would take in their community life.

And of course, such a thing is impossible on its face. We do not stand outside of space and time such that we may view the current state of the entire universe as an "object" given to consciousness. We are in the stream of the process -- Life -- part and parcel of it; in its totality, it cannot ever be a discrete, isolated "object of consciousness" for us. If we think it can, well -- that's what makes an ideologue.

And what about "evolutions" of human nature that have supposedly already taken place over the vastness of time til now? History covers only a fairly small part of this total spectrum. Over that small part, human nature has been highly consistent, if we may judge by the kinds of questions that human beings seem universally and perennially to ask (we can tell this from their art, their literature, their myths and legends, etc.) For instance, justice and morality as living issues go back at least to the second millennium B.C., i.e., to the First Intermediate Period (Egypt), with an anonymous inscription called "Dispute of a Man, Who Is Contemplating Suicide, with His Soul."

My theory is that morality is premised on human nature; if the nature changes, so does everything else. I keep testing the theory. So far, it has held up well. I am always prepared to entertain new evidence to further test it.

But dear PH, your "speculation" (above) is a fairy story, based on what you want to see, not an argument, based on what actually is. best, bb.

529 posted on 06/04/2002 7:15:26 AM PDT by betty boop
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 472 | View Replies]

To: Phaedrus
Evolutionists can tell us which species were fit and which were not but only after the fact, based on their "survival". They cannot tell us, now, which species exhibit reproductive fitness and will survive and which do not. So how much scientific meaning do such concepts have? Looking back, anyone can play Monday morning quarterback and impose patterns where they may or may not in fact exist.

Great reply, Phaedrus. All the way down to the Culture War. best, bb.

530 posted on 06/04/2002 7:26:56 AM PDT by betty boop
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 527 | View Replies]

To: tortoise; yendu bwam
tortise, I have a question about your nomenclature.

I think we discussed this subject a little bit on another thread a while back, but here you first frame the question as;
...whether or not the human mind is running on finite state machinery... [emphasis mine].

Then you state your belief (based on tests that you have seen) that the human mind is in fact a piece of complex finite state machinery.

In your latter phrasing you have, as a matter of identity, the mind as being the machine, whereas in your former you have the mind as running on top, so to speak, of the machine. Those seem to be two different things. Do you see the mind as the machine, or do you see the human mind as a property of the machine?

In my opinion, Machine and Person are two different classes. I think it is an error to conflate the two. A machine is an impersonal thing. A person, by definition, is not an impersonal thing, but personal. A machine cannot be a person. Every thing that a machine does is always and only an effect of a prior physical cause. If the mind of a human being is nothing but the effect, or the emergent property of physical force in a brain, what is it that causes those physical forces to produce different effects/thoughts? If man is nothing but machine, then the "it" MUST always be a prior physical cause. The logical conclusion of this view can only be that there is no real human personhood. If we are nothing but machine, always just an effect, riding along on top of those physical forces, then there is no real free will. Consequently there is no real morality, because moral obligation assumes various attributes of personhood that machines do not possess, including such things as personal volition, and the personal nature of the authority that commands the moral action, and so on. But every person reading this knows immediately and intuitively that machines do not possess personal volition, and so we would think it idiotic for example, to PUNISH a machine for doing what it ought not to do. As we know that machines always operate by coercive physical force, so also we know that machines do not have moral obligation. If your computer keyboard malfunctions and somehow manages to produce some random words on a page in your Microsoft Word document, and those words happen to resemble a sentence that contains a command, you are not going to feel any obligation to obey what the words tell you to do. You know intuitively that machines do not have moral authority. If a universal silicon Turing machine replies to my post here and issues its some command to me, I have no moral obligation to obey it.

All things human depends on the notion that we are personal beings and not machines. And that's a stab at explaining why I believe that Persons, are not just Machines.

Cordially,

531 posted on 06/04/2002 8:56:33 AM PDT by Diamond
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 523 | View Replies]

To: betty boop
My theory is that morality is premised on human nature; if the nature changes, so does everything else. I keep testing the theory. So far, it has held up well. I am always prepared to entertain new evidence to further test it. But dear PH, your "speculation" (above) is a fairy story, based on what you want to see, not an argument, based on what actually is.

We're talking about wildly different things when it comes to the future of humanity, and of course some speculation is inevitable here. A future branch of humanity, if isolated for a few million years on their own planet, just might speciate into something different enough that they couldn't breed with us. Star travel being what we think it is, there would likely be numerous planets that would be isolated for long periods, and if they were settled by a small number of similar individuals (Swedes on one world, pygmis on another, all Japanese somewhere else), it's a classic setup for evolution. But they wouldn't become a species of bears, or fish, and certainly not termites. They'd be, perhaps, as genetically different from us (and from the other isolated worlds) as we are from the Neanderthals. My guess is that, as intelligent creatures, we wouldn't allow ourselves to change into something too far different from what we are now. Better, perhaps. Bigger brains, better memory, eyesight, teeth, stronger hearts, etc. Those details can and probably should be improved. But they'd be recognizably human, even if you couldn't reproduce with one of them. But as I said, if they were intelligent they'd need to have the same values we do, thus the same morality. After maybe 50 or 100 million years of a planet's isolation, all bets are off, but I'm not trying to predict anything that far out.

532 posted on 06/04/2002 9:11:50 AM PDT by PatrickHenry
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 529 | View Replies]

To: PatrickHenry
Hey PH! Whether we're dealing with a time scale "going back" into the unknown human past, or a time scale "going forward" into the unknown human future, we are dealing (1) in terms of times scales that vastly exceed the ability of the mind to comprehend (2) in which most of what has occurred already is completely unknowable to people now living on the basis of direct experience; and what has not yet occurred is also completely unknowable, because it hasn't happened yet.

We have some indirect evidence of past events and circumstances for the historical period of human experience. But it is not exhaustive; for there was (presumably) a "before" before history began to be recorded.

Still, man infers and speculates from what he experiences and knows; which is where myths come from. And also science fiction. There are many instances in the past where "sci-fi" has proved prescient regarding future developments; and there are also "true myths," in the sense of truthful -- though certainly not exhaustive and certainly not necessarily "replicable" or "falsifiable" in the technical sense -- accounts of the way man experiences his place in the universe.

Where our knowedge is partial -- and it always is -- we have to "fill in the gaps" somehow. But in neither of these cases are we speaking of science or of scientific knowledge. JMHO FWIW. Thanks for writing, Patrick. best, bb.

533 posted on 06/04/2002 10:23:06 AM PDT by betty boop
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 532 | View Replies]

To: betty boop
My theory is that morality is premised on human nature; if the nature changes, so does everything else. I keep testing the theory. So far, it has held up well. I am always prepared to entertain new evidence to further test it.

I'm glad we're in basic agreement about this! The thing is, regarding human evolution that when it comes to answering something like "what's the best kind of government?", or "what are the best principles to live by when it comes to the opposite sex?", we have a vast store of history & comparative anthropology on which to draw. And all of this information concerns humans who are just like us, on an evolutionary timescale.

As far back as we can go in recorded history, we're still dealing with people who are Homo sapiens sapiens. If people who have access to this vast reach of knowledge - the broadly educated classes - still can't come to a general agreement on basic questions of morality & governance, then I don't know if knowing everything there is to know about biological evolution will fix it. (So it's gratifying to see that representative democracy & capitalism is taking over whole continents, if not the world just yet!)

Betty, I'm a software engineer. I write Windows programs, and lately I've been building a large Internet application in PHP & MySQL. Before that, COBOL on bigger machines. No matter which high-level language or operating system I work in, I tend to design, debug, and think in terms of the higher level concepts: What am I trying to accomplish? When it comes time to start debugging the code & track down errors or deficiencies, I still tend to think in terms of my high level code and how I failed on that level. Often it turns out to be a bug in that level of logic, but the most maddening bugs often turn out to be compiler errors - low level code. I often find these errors after days of agonizing over why things don't happen the way I programmed them - and why I can't even find the pattern for when they go wrong. At this point I have to go into Assembler mode, and look at the really low level code that got generated, and step thru the code on that level. When this happens I feel like a neurologist examining the squiggles on an EEG in order to figure out why the patient is having paranoid delusions!

The point is, there are appropriate levels at which to examine behavior, and appropriate tools with which to do it. Now that evolution has provided us with free will, I'm very skeptical that looking at evolution for answers to the best kind of society or moral code, etc. will provide much insight that history, economics, psychology, political science, and anthropology haven't already provided.

534 posted on 06/04/2002 11:13:55 AM PDT by jennyp
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 529 | View Replies]

To: betty boop
One aspect of our physiology that sounds fascinating, is the recent discovery that there really are pheromones, and that there is no single universal pheromone. It turns out that there are something like two dozen different body odors, and different people have one or more of these 24. Now, these body odors correspond to different sets of immunities, and the most sexy smells for any one person are precisely those odors that correspond to the most different sets of immunities from themselves.

(My understanding of this is purely Discover Channel quality, so don't take it as an expert's explanation. :-)

Now, they didn't need to understand evolution to detect this phenomenon in the first place, nor will it probably be needed in order to exploit the phenomenon, but it only makes sense in light of evolution. (The more your husband turns your motor, the healthier your children should be.)

I get conflicting claims about whether incest is more prevalent with adopted children vs. genetically related children. If we assume it is more prevalent, then this could explain why it would happen: The couple adopts a pre-pubescent child, who is not giving off any pheromones yet. Then when they do... uh-oh, it turns out to be from a different immunity set than the father! This shouldn't happen if they're their genetic offspring.

Ah, but maybe there's something more subtle going on: Is the immunity response set passed along via the chromosomes? Then, if a daughter happens to get most of her immunity genes from her mother, then she'd smell more like her mother does than like her father's sister would, and that could provide problematic temptation for him as well.

This would be an interesting experiment to perform: Compare the relevant genes (or body odors) of incest victims and their parents, and trace the pheromone combinations that ensue.

535 posted on 06/04/2002 11:30:33 AM PDT by jennyp
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 533 | View Replies]

To: jennyp
Now that evolution has provided us with free will, I'm very skeptical that looking at evolution for answers to the best kind of society or moral code, etc. will provide much insight that history, economics, psychology, political science, and anthropology haven't already provided.

Hi jennyp! Nice description. But a question -- HOW is free will a product of evolution? Would you say that self-awareness/self-reflective consciousness is also a product of evolution? If so, how do you know?

536 posted on 06/04/2002 12:17:48 PM PDT by betty boop
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 534 | View Replies]

To: Diamond; Tortoise
he logical conclusion of this view can only be that there is no real human personhood. If we are nothing but machine, always just an effect, riding along on top of those physical forces, then there is no real free will.

I also believe that it's very, very difficult to explain free will as emanating from an algorithmic machine (and without at least considering the realm of the quantum). One possibility of course is that free will as people experience it is just an illusion. But everything in our minds rebels against that possibility. One possibility that's been bandied about is that a conflux of self-referential algorithmic loops and such in the brain brings about consciousness and free will. For many reasons, I doubt that possibility as well. I'm not totally sure what Tortoise means by a 'finite state machine,' and admit I need to do some reading up on this. Then finally, on the question of free will, it becomes, in very general terms, hard to say that humans are only reacting to their environment in a prescribed way, when a great part of human existence is given over to moral questions, and avoiding the temptations to do evil or bad things.

537 posted on 06/04/2002 12:34:20 PM PDT by yendu bwam
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 531 | View Replies]

To: Diamond
In your latter phrasing you have, as a matter of identity, the mind as being the machine, whereas in your former you have the mind as running on top, so to speak, of the machine. Those seem to be two different things. Do you see the mind as the machine, or do you see the human mind as a property of the machine?

I don't have time address all the points brought up, but I want to make a couple quick comments that are important foundational concepts.

First, there is no real mathematical distinction between "hardware" and "software", and no clear break between the two in practice. They are the same thing and interchangeable i.e. everything that exists as hardware can be implemented in software and vice versa. I often see people treat them as different in these discussions, but that is largely a consequence of the peculiar structure of the computers that most humans are familiar with (i.e. the von Neumann architecture). This isn't a necessity, just a convenient way of working with silicon substrates.

Second, "free will" is an illusion that all self-aware FSMs will have as a consequence of what could be described as Godel's Incompleteness Theorem applied to state machinery. Being perfectly aware of your own state ("your own state" assuming a self-aware finite state machine) is mathematically impossible, though you can make good approximations as to what you will do next, and therefore you cannot have perfect prior knowledge of what you'll do next until you do it. In other words, what you might view as "free will" could be correctly viewed by a much more powerful outside observer as you following a deterministically predictable trajectory.

What "free will" really means is that you can't know exactly what you'll do next until you actually do it. "Choices" have predeterminable (to some entity at least) outcomes, but you won't be aware of it until you make a choice. This may not be easy to digest, but it is the logical mathematical outcome of self-awareness on finite state machines. It should be noted that non-FSMs are even worse in this regard, so positing a different underlying reality doesn't help much here. And in the end, the existence or not of "free will" doesn't really matter a whole lot; it might change the excuses, but not the reality.

538 posted on 06/04/2002 1:27:13 PM PDT by tortoise
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 531 | View Replies]

To: Diamond
Nice exposition at #531, Diamond.
539 posted on 06/04/2002 1:28:21 PM PDT by Phaedrus
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 531 | View Replies]

To: yendu bwam
I'm not totally sure what Tortoise means by a 'finite state machine,' and admit I need to do some reading up on this.

A finite state machine is a fundamental concept in computational theory. The mathematical definition (which you probably don't want) is any system with a non-infinite Kolmogorov complexity. A more pedestrian (and not quite correct) definition is any deterministic process that can be expressed in a finite (though possibly extremely large) amount of memory. Generally speaking, any finite state machine can be perfectly emulated on any other finite state machine that is larger. The reality is a bit more complicated, because we typically try and emulate large FSMs on smaller FSMs, which opens things up to all sorts of quirks and problems. Proper and useful coverage of FSMs is a lengthy topic with very interesting tangents that could easily spiral out of control on their own.

540 posted on 06/04/2002 1:55:37 PM PDT by tortoise
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 537 | View Replies]


Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first previous 1-20 ... 501-520521-540541-560561-577 next last

Disclaimer: Opinions posted on Free Republic are those of the individual posters and do not necessarily represent the opinion of Free Republic or its management. All materials posted herein are protected by copyright law and the exemption for fair use of copyrighted works.

Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

FreeRepublic, LLC, PO BOX 9771, FRESNO, CA 93794
FreeRepublic.com is powered by software copyright 2000-2008 John Robinson