Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

Skip to comments.

Wolfe in sheep's clothing? (On "The Future of Liberalism" by Alan Wolfe.)
The New Criterion ^ | March 2009 | William D. Gairdner

Posted on 03/01/2009 2:50:11 PM PST by neverdem

On The Future of Liberalism by Alan Wolfe.

A political ideology may usefully be defined as a structure of interdependent ideas. It is like a building: if you can falsify the foundational notions in critiquing it, the whole structure will collapse. Readers already comfortable with the political leanings and beliefs of Alan Wolfe, a political scientist at Boston College, will enjoy The Future of Liberalism because it will make them feel—especially since the election of Barack Obama—that they are safely ensconced on the cozy side of history.[1] His critics—I am one—will appreciate the book because it is rare to find quite so much earnest and contestable special-pleading for modern “liberalism” between two covers. It is a book that calls to mind the droll complaint that to do things like physics, or mathematics, or chemistry, you need a pencil, some paper, and a wastebasket. But to do political science, you don’t need the wastebasket.

A reviewer’s first duty to potential purchasers of a book, however, is to give them a clear sense of what it is about—and for that I am definitely going to need the wastebasket. Professor Wolfe has written a book interesting as much for its occasional nuggets of wisdom as for his display of polemical energy. From cover to cover he is galloping as hard as he can on what Laurence Sterne in his rollicking novel Tristram Shandy would certainly have described as his “hobby-horse.”

With respect to topic, tone, balance, and what Wolfe repeatedly calls “fairness,” he has done his evangelical best. He begins by defining and defending his terms by pigeonholing his mostly conservative enemies with humorless caricature, and throughout the book, he tries hard to distinguish and promote his personal and often heartfelt understanding of “liberalism” as the salvation of Western civilization. To his credit, what helps a reader stay the course until the end is Wolfe’s awareness of the objections he may be stimulating. He curtseys to them in a timely way, just as the reader has mentally lined them up. He also makes a point of frequently scolding liberals, not for being wrong, but for not being sufficiently Wolfian in their liberalism.

One of my main objections to the book as a whole, however, is that with the exception of a few of the better chapters that manage to stay on topic, page after page of this book feels like a rambling lecture from someone who has launched himself into the field of debate like a steel ball into a pinball machine of ideas. The ideas light up when the ball happens to hit them, but there is no hint of where it will head next. So I think the best way forward is to follow the ball and react to some of his core ideas.

Wolfe writes that liberalism should be championed “as a reminder of Americans’ connection to basic values that stretch back centuries.” The two core liberal values, he insists, are “freedom and equality,” and he locates them principally in the thinking of John Locke. The first objection to this statement is historical and moral. Locke himself and almost all the American Founders had a conception of virtue and the common good that was as clearly distinguished as can be imagined from the merely individual good and that, as President Clap of Yale asserted in 1765, demanded “conformity to the moral perfection of God.” The most important “basic value” back then was that anyone uttering Wolfe’s brand of hyper-individual, modern secular “tolerant” liberalism would have been considered an anti-social abominator out to destroy the bonds of community. The second objection is philosophical and was voiced in 1850 by Frédéric Bastiat when his philosophy of liberty was attacked by Alphonse de Lamartine because it did not include equality, and so, Lamartine argued, could not proceed to fraternity. Bastiat replied that the second part of such a program would always destroy the first, making the third impossible.

I have always told my children that liberty and equality (in the substantive sense of the latter that Wolfe says distinguishes liberals from conservatives today) are joined like a teeter-totter. As one goes up, the other must go down. This doesn’t seem to bother Wolfe, who in discussing the rights conceived by the French and American Revolutions claims that “there is a direct line from the ideals of those revolutions to the welfare states of the contemporary world.”

There is insufficient space here to demonstrate adequately the profoundly erroneous nature of this assertion. Suffice it to say that the American founding principle of equality had nothing to do with equalizing outcomes, and the French meaning of equality (spelled out in Article VI of the Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen) specifically stated that equality meant before the law only, and that all citizens are admissible to “dignities, positions, and employments, according to their ability, and on the basis of no other distinctions than that of their virtues and talents.” Not a scrap of affirmative action there (which did not, however, prevent the French from trying it).

Wolfe’s brand of liberalism is something else. He asserts that “as many people as possible should have as much say as is feasible over the direction their lives will take,” and that “if this requires an active role for government, then modern liberals are prepared to accept state intervention” (in the economy, moral life, sexual life, family life, regulation of speech, education, hiring, affirmative action, and many more domains). So there is the plain and simple —very simple—and quite contradictory, equation: government direction (that is, coercion) will make you free. Wolfe justifies this pro-state position with repetitive litanies of the fears and horrors consequent upon the folly of conservatism: unemployment, low pay, disease, old age, ignorance, hunger, poverty, war, prejudice, and so on. For good measure (just to show more “fairness”), he does offer plenty of policy directives by which even liberals “ought” to abide. (“Ought” is the most frequent word in his polemic). There is some honest insight, too. With respect to the “direct line” to the welfare state he imagines, Wolfe does mention the real reason for it, and it has to do with crass opportunism, and not with theory: “Once people get the idea into their heads that they deserve dignity and respect, they will see no reason to stop with procedure and [will] go all the way to substance.” But he has no objection to this.

Hence, two conclusions. As Harvard’s Professor Harvey Mansfield has put it:

From having been the aggressive doctrine of vigorous, spirited men, liberalism has become hardly more than a trembling in the presence of illiberalism. Who today is called a liberal for strength and confidence in defense of liberty?

Just so, by this standard, Wolfe is a modern anti-liberal, with a touch of the old Marxist nonsense thrown in about how free markets always keep wages in “a vicious spiral” of low earning. By now he is so lost in theories, he deplores the “dependencies” created by markets (the yearning for higher wages) and by charities (that cause us to “beg for more”) and says the welfare state is “an exercise in self-governance” (he really did say this) that seeks to bypass such dependencies.

But it is when he states that “the welfare state is an institutionalization of the moral idea of empathy” that I realize we are just thinking past each other, because for me the welfare state is the institutionalization, not of empathy but of political power in the wily guise of empathy. Its real operation—aimed at capturing the allegiance of all citizens—is to substitute progressively its own programs and functions for those voluntarily created by the people themselves in their civil associations, thereby to so weaken and atomize the myriad little platoons of a once-free society that individuals will be bribed into gradually letting go of the real ties that bind and will switch allegiance to the coercive humanitarianism of the state, the supposedly all-providing benefactor of their lives. Just so, modern politics, Wolfe admits,

is all about dividing up and relying upon what the state has to offer, not about cutting back what it provides.

At this point, some understanding of how the original heroic anti-statist liberalism became Wolfe’s groveling statist type is essential, for he seems unbothered by sacrificing the freedom of some, who ought to have “as much say as is feasible over the direction their lives will take” for the “equality” of others. The answer is that the modern liberal Director General will always decide what is “feasible,” and Wolfe is unfazed by the fact that this is largely a zero-sum game in which governments that have no money of their own must first take it from taxpayers (or print it or borrow it to create deficits, which are just deferred taxes) and then distribute it to those they deem worthy. In other words, to get modern liberalism you always have first to rob a Peter to pay a Paul. A true classical liberal was someone who began by protesting just this sort of legal plunder and would have despised Wolfe’s program. So what happened? How did classical liberalism mutate into its triumphalist modern form?

Partly it was because there was afloat at the time a corollary anti-Christian idea, a belief that all humans are born pure and without sin. Rousseau had famously argued in his Social Contract that we are born free and naturally good but soon a rotten society corrupts and enchains us, such that we must create a better world by bonding together in a unanimous General Will. In his novel Emile, he urged all free individuals to

transport the I into the common unity, with the result that each individual believes himself no longer one but a part of the unity and no longer feels except within the whole.

Wolfe seems blind to the terrible consequences of this idea. Indeed, he mocks Edmund Burke’s prescient warning of the time that Rousseau was “an insane Socrates” and accuses conservatives of believing that The Social Contract “contained a plot outline for the French Revolution.” More careful historians such as Robert Nisbet have indeed concluded that Rousseau’s theories supplied the foundation for the plot:

It is in Rousseau’s absorption of all forms of society into the unitary mould of the state that we may observe the first unmistakable appearance of the totalitarian theory of society.

Rousseau wanted to unify the people in a democracy of the One, and the French Revolution and the Terror were its predictable consequences, a historical demonstration awash in blood of the impossibility of producing fraternity by conflating liberty and equality.

John Stuart Mill, another of Wolfe’s heroes, also argued in his famous if self-contradictory, tract On Liberty against a host of tangled social and moral “oppressions.” But he was aware of the horrors of the Terror and so took an alternative approach (even as he turned increasingly socialist). He opted for a democracy of the Many. Not for him any common moral bond or mystical General Will. Instead, he insisted that morality is entirely a private matter unless we harm someone else and initiated the modern doctrinal erosion of the ancient notion that morality is a public good held in common. Mill’s revolutionary notion has proved so attractive that we no longer expect to have, nor can we any longer identify, a unified communal, or national, moral ground—except Mill’s private moral relativism.

Just as this privatization of morality was taking place, those original freedom-fighting liberals saw that the human flourishing they expected to arise from more freedom was a resounding disappointment. With more freedom came more inequality of condition. As many people got poor as got rich. Most galling of all, they saw that many freely preferred the luxuries of laziness, ignorance, and charity to the sacrifices and demands of work and education. So embarrassed and ashamed were they by this result, this insult to their theory of freedom, that they turned to the state for support. They were still convinced we are free, but that for the creation of their earthly paradise some prodding or social engineering would be necessary.

Hence, our Wolfian “libertarian socialism,” by now a condition in which most moral and sexual issues are considered under a libertarian standard of total privacy and freedom, while matters such as social security, medical care, income distribution, welfare, material standards of living, and the like are considered public objectives to be secured by the state. Another way of putting this is to say that we now have a polity in which citizens are assumed to have all the rights and governments, all of the duties. This is, alas, our world, and in defending the indefensible Wolfe amply illustrates its moral and political confusion. Let us turn to just a few examples from the hundreds in his book.

The first irony arises when Wolfe asks us to remove our individual rights and to

imagine a world in which religion (or irreligion) is coerced, freedom of speech curtailed, economic activity directed and controlled by the state, and no one [he means unions] allowed to organize and bargain collectively to improve their economic condition—and you have a political system that can only be called illiberal …

Well, I took his suggestion and did try to imagine it, and, with the exception of the bit about unions, I recognized illiberal Canada, where I live, and much of the United States, which, for decades, has been trying to catch up with Canada’s headlong embrace of libertarian socialism.

To wit: Christianity, the religious and moral foundation of both nations, has been all but forced from the public square, and secular humanism is mandated by law and edict in its place (irreligion is coerced). All Canadian provinces and the federal government now have “Human Rights Commissions” that specifically, and with considerable zeal, curtail all speech that is not deemed sufficiently “liberal.” The embarrassing, illiberal public prosecutions of the well-known author Mark Steyn for his critiques of Islam and of Ezra Levant for republishing the Danish cartoons are cases in point. Most American jurisdictions have versions of these same extra-legal tribunals, and the universities in both countries—once bastions of free speech—are now among the most illiberal purveyors of political correctness imaginable: mini-Star Chambers dotted all across our once-free lands, everywhere fining people and mandating liberal “re-education” as a cure. In Canada, not a few mayors have been fined thousands of dollars for refusing to stage gay-pride parades in their towns, and one woman has spent a total of six years in prison for peacefully and repeatedly protesting abortion on the public sidewalk in front of a clinic. Some curtailment.

As for economic activity, the history of both nations over the past century has been unidirectional: increasing control over enterprise by way of massive centralization and regulation of economic policy and law—over states/provinces, municipalities, individuals, and corporations—combined with tax regimes (and public debt) so onerous and punitive that neither country can be said to be economically free in any original sense of the word. I sold my first business because the government was telling me whom I had to hire (under policies of affirmative action, feminism, and multiculturalism), what wages I had to pay (under “pay equity”); it was even dictating the maximum allowable price of my product. I surrendered and got out. In terms of total tax burden (all forms of tax, obvious and hidden, from all levels of government), the citizens of both countries are now working for their governments almost six months of the year. I don’t have to “imagine” Wolfe’s illiberal world, because millions of us have been living in it for some time, and it is structurally and morally dangerous to true liberal values.

Structurally, we are endangered because many of the Western democracies are becoming tripartite states in which one-third of all taxpayers are employed by government at some level, one-third of the people are crucially dependent in some way on government support (welfare, Medicare, Medicaid, farm subsidies, and a gazillion other untrackable support programs), and one-third produces the income (the tax base) paid out in supports for the first two-thirds. Anyone can see that, as this develops in a mass “democratic” system, the first two-thirds will always gang up on the last.

The grievous moral hazard of so many modern welfare states that now carry so-called structural debt (because no political leader will risk demanding cuts in state services or that the people start sacrificing and working harder to pay it off) is that the cost of much of our current consumption will have to be paid by future generations of citizens who are not here to defend themselves against our appetites. In short, as a direct consequence of what Wolfe calls “liberalism’s commitment to improving who we are,” liberals are willing to treat the children of tomorrow as a means to his “liberal” ends today. Shame on them.

Wolfe then proceeds to argue we ought to improve who we are by eschewing, where possible, the “nature” arguments of many conservative biologists and sociobiologists (he rightly exposes Darwinists such as the intemperate Richard Dawkins as flounderers in their own philosophical contradictions). Instead, we must rely on the nurture of “artifice”—on man-made social, moral, and political improvements. To his credit, he is aware that in this area there are “profound questions for which there are no easy answers,” and he even scolds the left for having fallen for biological schemes of improving nature via the artifice of “liberal eugenics.” He does not mention that about 36 percent of all U.S. abortions are of black children, nor does he complain of abortion being used everywhere for sex selection against females.

At this point, he ought to be squirming, because although he supports a woman’s “choice” in abortion—“under liberalism women must be allowed to control their own bodies”—he fails to explain why his own moral standard ought not to apply just as surely to an unborn child’s body. Now modern liberals must be pushed to drill down here. They froth in outrage that slavery was/is a perniciously anti-liberal institution. And yet the fundamental legal device that makes slavery possible is the formal declaration in law of the non-personhood of the slave. But this is exactly, in every last detail, the same legal device liberals such as Wolfe rely upon to justify abortion. Beyond the sole distinction of the existence of the victim either inside or outside the womb, there is no effective difference between a declaration of non-personhood that creates a class of born-alive victims that enables, sustains, and makes invisible to its perpetrators a regime of chattel slavery and a declaration of non-personhood that creates a class of alive, but not-yet-born imminent victims, and thereby enables, sustains, and makes invisible to its perpetrators the abortion regimes currently defended in the name of liberal democracy.

I have dwelt mostly on the first part of Wolfe’s book, because his theoretical understandings and misunderstandings condition all his later policy prescriptions. In successive chapters that are not without interest, he zeroes in on the nationalistic militarism inspired by Romantic poetry and art to which he feels too many neoconservatives and even liberals have fallen prey. His chapter “Mr. Schmitt Goes to Washington” was the most engaging for me, because Carl Schmitt’s ideas about the faults of liberal democracy are so interesting to thinkers both left and right. We can only guess, however, what Wolfe would say about “liberal democracies” such as the United States and Canada, where so much legislative authority has passed from the elected representatives of the people to judges, that is—What would he say is “self-directed” about our passage from parliamentary (or congressional) sovereignty, to judicial sovereignty? He also argues extensively that conservatives cannot govern because they don’t want as much government as liberals do. But that is because they prefer what used to be liberal principles of self-reliance, local control, and personal responsibility to a controlling central government that sweeps in to solve all their problems, thus to rob them of the ability to direct their own lives toward their own ends.

I close by saying that in the shameless—or rather, in the proud—guise of political and moral neutrality and openness, Mr. Wolfe’s The Future of Liberalism, though claiming to follow a venerable individualist liberal tradition, instead augurs for the soft-socialist and oppressive statism that is its badly deformed child. Those who welcome this state of affairs will find all the usual saccharine justifications between these covers, and those who deplore it will find that Wolfe offers plenty of material with which to criticize it.

 

Notes
Go to the top of the document.

 

  1. The Future of Liberalism, by Alan Wolfe; Knopf, 335 pages, $25.95. Go back to the text.

William D. Gairdner isWilliam Gairdner's writing can be found at more from this author

This article originally appeared in The New Criterion, Volume 27 March 2009, on page 4

Copyright © 2009 The New Criterion | www.newcriterion.com http://www.newcriterion.com/articles.cfm/Wolfe-in-sheep-s-clothing--4027



TOPICS: Crime/Corruption; Culture/Society; Editorial; Politics/Elections
KEYWORDS: alanwolfe; futureofliberalism; libertariansocialism; wolfe
IMHO, libertarian socialism is an oxymoron. Conflict is certain.
1 posted on 03/01/2009 2:50:12 PM PST by neverdem
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | View Replies]

To: neverdem
Jonah Goldberg has written a very heavily annotated history text on the future of liberalism in the United States. Allan Wolfe does not measure up to its ankles


2 posted on 03/01/2009 3:18:54 PM PST by Candor7 (Fascism? All it takes is for good men to say nothing, ( member NRA)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: neverdem

I’ve been reading Johnson’s profiles of Western “intellectuals” like Rousseau and Marx, and what comes away with is that most of these individuals are profoundly unhappy, supremely egotistical to the point of utter lack of empathy or regard and who hate actual people and compensate for this lack of love by CLAIMING to love all of humanity.

Rousseau is the father of totalitarianism and was an utterly wicked man who abandoned all of his children to early death, stole and lied about his life. Marx lied about his cites in his books, never stepped outside of his library to get a sense of what life was like for the ‘workers’ or anyone else and basically had a poetic eschatological vision that he then went out to support with his works of ‘philosophy’ that were nothing but an expression of his love of domination and violence and the hope that after the revolution HE would rule.

What you take away is that there is a ‘vision’ and all of their service and labor is dedicated to that vision (whatever it may be, not always the stereotypically Marxist) and all other human beings are worthy of contempt outside of the role they can play in enacting this drama upon all of human civilization.

It’s like Juan Williams on Fox saying in response to the assertion that tax breaks were simply about people keeping more of Their money: “it’s all our money!”

We will always have a difficult time with the will to power in which the human ego and self-crafted ideals and morals place each solipsistic soul at the heart of their own metaphysical drama. And make no mistake, they can call themselves libertarian socialists or anarchists, they power they assume over the lives and decisions of others always manifests in state power or murderous chaos.

You can never really rationally debate these folks. You can only hope to teach their followers who may or may not be well-intentioned but poorly informed or need a building up of humility and of a moral compass.

So what’s the response? This will to power and magical thinking will not just go away because of history and it hasn’t thus far. Millenarian tyrants and their religions will be with us for some time. They typically are not defeated at the ballot box but by terrible bloodshed or by a sapping of all belief in their bankrupt notions of “human unity and progress.” Sapping that belief is difficult when it is not practiced first. There goes the dilemma!


3 posted on 03/01/2009 4:34:20 PM PST by Skywalk (Transdimensional Jihad!)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: Candor7

Certainly better than Wolfe.

I was fascinated to spend hours in the late night (for some reason) reading the reactions by a few academics on crookedtimber.org to Goldberg’s book. While I would never rule out legitimate criticism of Goldberg’s efforts (nothing is perfect and maybe he was trying to slyly score some partisan points there) the sum of what I encountered was of people of some moderate intellectual gifts and academic training becoming arbiters of good scholarship and only allowing those ‘conservative’ viewpoints in outlets they have deemed permissible for being dispassionate.

Then you go to their own personal blogs and they are at Obama’s inauguration, reading the most paranoiac interpretations of Bush policy and utterly distorting the positions of their political opponents—but on a remarkably juvenile level.

It all boils down to “we sit in judgment and we have consensus and have been immersed in academe and therefore we find you lacking.”

It is telling that the most comments they’ve ever been able to generate have been about GOldberg’s book and this includes their own lefty booster posts and personal blogs.


4 posted on 03/01/2009 5:06:58 PM PST by Skywalk (Transdimensional Jihad!)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 2 | View Replies]

To: neverdem

Is there a FR “intellectual” ping list because essays like this should be required reading. I love Steyn but he’s a polemicist foremost. I enjoy reading essays with a slightly more dispassionate and academic approach as well. For too long, we’ve let the Left corner that market in what really have only amounted to screeds with a gloss of academic jargon (usually crit. theory.)


5 posted on 03/01/2009 5:08:42 PM PST by Skywalk (Transdimensional Jihad!)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: Skywalk
Goldbergs book is a significant work, a well annotated history.

I believe that Goldberg has proven beyond a doubt where fascism originates. It requires an acquiescent liberalized middle glass placed in fear, and a nationalist view of progress. Of course Obama exhibits all the necessary philosophical and personal markers of fascist history.

It is signidficant also that Goldberg proves that fascist movements in Europe had to destroy the right wing traditionalists, before they could fully blossom into totalitarian states. That destruction is now being attempted by Obama on our economy and on conservative culture. And Rush Limbaugh is the lightning rod.

Few Americans truly understand this. Rush Limbaugh does. Certainly Jonah Goldberg does.

6 posted on 03/01/2009 6:11:17 PM PST by Candor7 (Fascism? All it takes is for good men to say nothing, ( member NRA)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 4 | View Replies]

To: Calpernia

Conservative Academic Ping!


7 posted on 03/01/2009 6:12:27 PM PST by Candor7 (Fascism? All it takes is for good men to say nothing, ( member NRA)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: neverdem
Don't give the liberals a break on anything. You don't get more equality under their ideology. The sacrifice freedom, not for more equality, but for nothing.

The commies were all for Equality. Equal pay for everyone. Stalin changed that around 1930, when he started paying workers more, who produced more. So, they got a stifling, horrific communist tyranny AND the same old economic inequality, along with a New Class of bureaucrats, who got rich off having power.

We're there already with the Obama Administration. Rules Laws don't apply to the politically connected. Geithner and the all the others, who didn't pay their taxes and they had nothing happen to them. Don't try that at home.

These people are utter fools. They're depraved.

8 posted on 03/01/2009 7:12:31 PM PST by Jabba the Nutt (Obama is the American Allende.)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: Skywalk; wardaddy; Joe Brower; Cannoneer No. 4; Criminal Number 18F; Dan from Michigan; Eaker; ...
Is there a FR “intellectual” ping list because essays like this should be required reading.

You can call me curious.

RIP Paul Harvey I first remembered hearing him when I was in Vietnam. I'll miss him.

Alexander Hamilton, Modern America’s Founding Father

How Did This Happen? (The economic mess)

Rush Limbaugh addresses CPAC

Some noteworthy articles about politics, foreign or military affairs, IMHO, FReepmail me if you want on or off my list.

9 posted on 03/02/2009 1:01:17 AM PST by neverdem (Xin loi minh oi)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 5 | View Replies]

To: neverdem; Candor7; Skywalk; Jabba the Nutt

Great read. Thanks for the ping, neverdem. Great thread. Thanks for looking at the blogs of the detractors of Goldberg’s book (I have not read it), Skywalk. Very interesting.


10 posted on 03/02/2009 5:13:47 AM PST by PGalt
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 9 | View Replies]

To: Skywalk
We will always have a difficult time with the will to power in which the human ego and self-crafted ideals and morals place each solipsistic soul at the heart of their own metaphysical drama. And make no mistake, they can call themselves libertarian socialists or anarchists, they power they assume over the lives and decisions of others always manifests in state power or murderous chaos.

You can never really rationally debate these folks. You can only hope to teach their followers who may or may not be well-intentioned but poorly informed or need a building up of humility and of a moral compass.

So what’s the response? This will to power and magical thinking will not just go away because of history and it hasn’t thus far. Millenarian tyrants and their religions will be with us for some time. They typically are not defeated at the ballot box but by terrible bloodshed or by a sapping of all belief in their bankrupt notions of “human unity and progress.” Sapping that belief is difficult when it is not practiced first. There goes the dilemma!

BUMP-TO-THE-TOP!

11 posted on 03/02/2009 6:15:19 AM PST by PGalt
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 3 | View Replies]

To: neverdem

From the article...

The second objection is philosophical and was voiced in 1850 by Frédéric Bastiat when his philosophy of liberty was attacked by Alphonse de Lamartine because it did not include equality, and so, Lamartine argued, could not proceed to fraternity. Bastiat replied that the second part of such a program would always destroy the first, making the third impossible.

BUMP!


12 posted on 03/02/2009 6:17:04 AM PST by PGalt
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: neverdem

Thanks for the ping!


13 posted on 03/02/2009 7:23:44 AM PST by Alamo-Girl
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 9 | View Replies]

To: neverdem
The contradiction of modern liberalism is that it cannot understand the fact that liberty in the natural state is quite achievable, whereas equality is an ideal that cannot be achieved as it can never be a reality. One can aspire to both, but to be truly free is to be unequal. Classical liberalism as aspired to by our founders never included equality as an end, only equality of opportunity and aspirations. Equality as an end is the product of the perversion of the French revolution. "Liberté,Egalité, Fraternité" all mutually unattainable goals. We've been living with the legacy of that disaster ever since.
14 posted on 03/02/2009 7:35:33 AM PST by Cacique (quos Deus vult perdere, prius dementat ( Islamia Delenda Est ))
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: Skywalk

Dito


15 posted on 03/02/2009 7:46:30 AM PST by Cacique (quos Deus vult perdere, prius dementat ( Islamia Delenda Est ))
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 3 | View Replies]

To: AdmSmith; Berosus; Convert from ECUSA; dervish; Ernest_at_the_Beach; Fred Nerks; justiceseeker93; ..
Thanks neverdem.
It is a book that calls to mind the droll complaint that to do things like physics, or mathematics, or chemistry, you need a pencil, some paper, and a wastebasket. But to do political science, you don't need the wastebasket.

16 posted on 03/02/2009 2:39:07 PM PST by SunkenCiv (https://secure.freerepublic.com/donate/____________________ Profile updated Monday, January 12, 2009)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 9 | View Replies]

To: Skywalk

Worth another BUMP! (while I’m scrolling back looking for another subject)


17 posted on 03/05/2009 4:26:50 PM PST by PGalt
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 4 | View Replies]

To: neverdem
Thanks for posting it.

Be sure to check out the reviews in Commentary and National Review.

One reviewer conjured up a picture of Wolfe having filled all these index cards with observations and struggling to form a book out of them.

So, for example, he has a lot of information about Carl Schmitt and a lot of observations about Rousseau and Kant, but doesn't succeed in applying them to today's politics without forcing things.

Plus, the "good liberal" "bad conservative" dualism limits his ability to make use of the knowledge and insights he does have.

18 posted on 03/05/2009 4:34:36 PM PST by x
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

Disclaimer: Opinions posted on Free Republic are those of the individual posters and do not necessarily represent the opinion of Free Republic or its management. All materials posted herein are protected by copyright law and the exemption for fair use of copyrighted works.

Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

FreeRepublic, LLC, PO BOX 9771, FRESNO, CA 93794
FreeRepublic.com is powered by software copyright 2000-2008 John Robinson