Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

Skip to comments.

A Libertarian Constitution
The Claremont Institute ^ | 6/1/05 | Nelson Lund

Posted on 06/01/2005 2:55:30 PM PDT by P_A_I

A Libertarian Constitution

A review of Restoring the Lost Constitution: The Presumption of Liberty by Randy E. Barnett

By Nelson Lund

This review appeared in the Spring 2005 issue of the Claremont Review of Books.

Randy Barnett is one of the legal academy's leading libertarian theorists. His latest book is an exceedingly ambitious effort to show that the United States Constitution, rightly understood, protects individual liberty to a far greater extent than the Supreme Court has ever recognized.
Through a complex series of arguments, Barnett attempts to demonstrate that the Constitution requires courts to adopt what he calls a "Presumption of Liberty," which should lead them to nullify every law abridging any of an open-ended class of natural rights unless the government can demonstrate that the law meets stringent criteria of necessity and propriety.

Restoring the Lost Constitution advances three main theses. First, Barnett presents a theory of legitimacy, arguing that laws are "binding in conscience" only if there is a sufficient reason to believe that they do not unnecessarily, or improperly, violate the natural rights of the governed.

Second, he maintains that the Constitution requires courts to protect these natural rights by invalidating all federal laws that unnecessarily or improperly abridge them.

Finally, he contends that the Constitution also requires the same aggressive judicial approach to state laws that it requires with respect to federal laws.

Because I shall criticize some crucial elements in Barnett's argument, I should emphasize at the outset that this intelligent, thought-provoking book deserves to be read carefully by anyone who believes that the Constitution is a higher form of law than Supreme Court decisions.

As the Declaration of Independence announces, and as other evidence confirms, there was a broad consensus among the founding generation that the principal purpose of human government is to secure certain inherent or natural human rights.
The most obvious reflections of this consensus in the Constitution itself are the limited grant of enumerated powers to Congress, the separation of powers, and the enumeration of several individual rights.
In addition, Barnett believes, the judiciary has been commanded to identify and protect a vast, unenumerated body of natural rights by the 9th Amendment, which provides: "The enumeration in the Constitution of certain rights shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people."
Because he thinks this provision establishes a constitutional Presumption of Liberty, Barnett vigorously objects to the Supreme Court's consistent refusal to rely on the 9th Amendment in deciding cases.

The 9th Amendment is a companion to the 10th Amendment, which provides: "The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people."
As the 10th Amendment affirms that the Constitution's enumeration of powers is exhaustive, so the 9th Amendment affirms that its enumeration of rights is not exhaustive. This makes perfect sense because individual rights and government authority are correlative: if a government does not have the authority to issue certain commands to its citizens, they have a right not to be subjected to those commands by that government.

Thus, the 9th and 10th Amendments together serve as an emphatic, and indeed justiciable, reminder that the Constitution protects a vast number of unenumerated rights from infringement by the federal government, namely all those rights that the federal government is not authorized to abridge in the exercise of its enumerated powers. Some of them may be natural rights, some are positive rights established by state law, and some are political rights exercised in the course of establishing state law. The language of the 9th Amendment does not give a privileged status to any one of these categories of rights.

Two principal sources of the vast expansion of federal power have been the Commerce Clause and the so-called Sweeping Clause: "The Congress shall have Power…. To regulate Commerce with foreign Nations, and among the several States, and with the Indian Tribes," and "To make all Laws which shall be necessary and proper for carrying into Execution the foregoing Powers, and all other Powers vested by this Constitution in the Government of the United States, or in any Department or Officer thereof."
The Supreme Court has interpreted these provisions to allow Congress to regulate or prohibit virtually any commercial activity, including wholly intrastate activities, and a vast range of non-commercial activities as well. The Court's theory, in a nutshell, is that such activities may "affect" commerce among the several states and that it is therefore necessary and proper for Congress to control them.

Barnett provides a detailed demonstration that this theory is a departure from the original meaning of the Constitution, and he offers a number of thoughtful and generally plausible suggestions about how best to construe and apply the Commerce and Sweeping Clauses. If the Court were to accept something reasonably close to the original meaning of these provisions, the federal government would have a lot less power than it exercises today, and the people would correspondingly have much more freedom from federal interference in their lives.

* * *

The most radical thesis in Barnett's book is that judges are charged by the Constitution with protecting a vast range of unenumerated natural rights from interference by state law.

Barnett also has a different, and somewhat more plausible basis for concluding that the Constitution commands judges to protect natural rights from state interference.
The 14th Amendment provides: "No State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States…." Barnett argues that these privileges and immunities are the very same natural rights that he thinks are also protected by the 9th Amendment, a conclusion that he rests primarily on evidence from the legislative history of the 14th Amendment.
He vigorously attacks the Supreme Court's contrary interpretation, and especially the landmark 1873 Slaughterhouse decision, which held that the only privileges and immunities protected by this clause are those peculiarly attributable to national citizenship, like the right to travel to the national capital.

Even if one accepted Barnett's claim that the 14th Amendment was meant to authorize judges to nullify state laws that abridge certain unenumerated substantive rights, one would still have to ask how judges are supposed to identify these rights.
Barnett's answer is that everybody has a presumptive right to engage in any conduct that does not interfere with the rights of other persons, unless the government can show that a specific regulation is needed to facilitate everyone's exercise of the right.

The privileges and immunities protected by the 14th Amendment, Barnett maintains, can be identified by looking at state common law. This cannot be right.
The common law is a collection of rules adopted by judges in the course of deciding cases that are not covered by a state constitution or statute. These rules vary somewhat from state to state, and they can be altered or abolished in any state by its legislature. Because the 14th Amendment expressly imposes a restriction on state law, the substance of what it protects cannot possibly be determined by state law (unless the Privileges or Immunities Clause is only an anti-discrimination provision rather than a substantive guarantee, an interpretation that Barnett implicitly rejects).

While Barnett notes, accurately enough, that state common-law judges constantly make decisions distinguishing rightful from wrongful conduct, he neglects the significance of the fact that they are always doing so in the shadow of the state legislature's plenary authority (which is frequently exercised) to alter or preempt those decisions by statute. If these common-law decisions were suddenly to become the unalterable determinants of the rights protected by the 14th Amendment, state judges would be elevated to the role of philosopher-kings.
Yet, if the distinction between rightful and wrongful conduct were defined by the common law as altered or preempted by state statutes, the Privileges or Immunities Clause would place no constraints at all on state governments, which would make an absurdity of the 14th Amendment provision.

* * *

Elsewhere, the book takes a different approach to identifying the relevant privileges and immunities. Courts and commentators have long assumed that the Constitution leaves largely intact something called the "police power" of the state governments, which is a general authority to regulate and govern the citizenry. Barnett suggests that 14th Amendment privileges and immunities are those rights not subject to this power.

But what exactly is the police power's scope? It is never mentioned, let alone defined, in the Constitution. Barnett articulates and embraces what he calls a Lockean theory of the police power, but his only authorities for imputing this theory to the Constitution are judicial decisions and academic commentaries. And even those authorities generally give the states much more discretion to abridge people's liberties than Barnett is willing to allow. It is perfectly obvious that the states would be well advised to limit government power and protect important individual rights in their state constitutions.
In fact, all the states have done just that, though not to the extent that Barnett thinks they should. Whatever the merits of his view of the proper scope of government power, and whether or not his is a correct interpretation of Locke, showing that the Constitution enacted his view into law would require far more evidence than Barnett provides.

Restoring the Lost Constitution is an impressive attempt to demonstrate that our written Constitution enacted into law a sweeping and highly libertarian theory of natural rights and limited government.
I have passed more lightly than I would have liked over Barnett's attractively coherent analytical approach, which contrasts with the frequently sloppy Supreme Court opinions that our legal system treats as the authoritative expression of constitutional law. It is sad how much of our fundamental law has gotten lost beneath an obscuring blanket of Supreme Court decisions, and Barnett's effort to recover the lost Constitution is a noble undertaking, even if it is not completely successful.


TOPICS: Constitution/Conservatism
KEYWORDS: govwatch; judiciary; libertarian; scotus
Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first previous 1-20 ... 81-100101-120121-140141-146 last
To: FredZarguna

Fred, either we abide by the U.N. or we don't. Saying we justified our action on the basis of U.N. actions doesn't wash without U.N. permission to war against Iraq. We didn't have it. It's like arresting a murderer, throwing him in jail, and saying it's okay you shot him in his cell because you could have shot him if he were running. There's a line you cross when you cherrypick law. Our strike was not legally authorized by the U.N.

Nor should we be concerned that it wasn't. I'd far rather the U.S. makes its own decisions on with whom we decide war, anyway. Screw the U.N.--the nationstate shouldn't die on the altar of the globalist priesthood of bureaucrats, especially a corrupt one like that of the U.N. or the E.U.


141 posted on 06/08/2005 3:24:07 PM PDT by LibertarianInExile (<-- sick of faux-conservatives who want federal government intervention for 'conservative things.')
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 139 | View Replies]

To: P_A_I
Libertarians are right wing liberals..
If it was not true then right-wing liberal would be an Oxy-moron..
Libertarians MAKE it true.. Anarchists that appear sane..
142 posted on 06/08/2005 3:55:55 PM PDT by hosepipe (This propaganda has been ok'ed me to included some fully orbed hyperbole....)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: FredZarguna
A statement of agreement with a particular belief is not a "pledge/oath/vow" by any of their definitions. Use your dictionary.

What the Pennsylvania LP chooses to call the statement does not define for me the meaning of the word "oath." Quite possibly they want people to take the statement seriously and not just sign off on it. By calling it an oath, it may cause people to take a second and closer look at it. But it obviously didn't work with you, as your imagination has ran wild replacing all kinds of words in it so as to remake it into something that is closer to a pacifist oath. Those words not in it that you said were are "aggressive", "engage", and "will". With this latter word making it clearly a pledge by any definitive standard, and thereby bringing it closer to being an oath in fact. (read your own posted definition of the word "promise" and then look up "oath" in your dictionary). But as I said your dreamed up words just are not in it.

Now with thirty years affiliation with so many local LPs, one must wonder how you couldn't even get the source right as to the origin of the agreement on beliefs. I had to correct you in reply #86. But after I corrected you on it, you ramble on about a second part to the quote that does not exist. It seems to me that with 30 years you would know what you signed, what it means, as well as the original source for it. I guess not.

As for the rest of your reply, my silence does not imply agreement, as you so dishonestly implied earlier in the thread. I just do not feel it necessary.

143 posted on 06/08/2005 4:17:26 PM PDT by jackbob
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 138 | View Replies]

To: hosepipe
hosepipe wrote:

Libertarians are right wing liberals..
If it was not true then right-wing liberal would be an Oxy-moron..
Libertarians MAKE it true.. Anarchists that appear sane.






Some libertarians proudly call themselves:

'Classical Liberals'
Address:http://www.belmont.edu/lockesmith/essay.html



Your comment on Anarchists does not say much for your own sanity, imo.
144 posted on 06/08/2005 4:40:48 PM PDT by P_A_I
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 142 | View Replies]

To: P_A_I
[ Your comment on Anarchists does not say much for your own sanity, imo. ]

Have followed Libertarian "ideas" over the years..
They have become more "conservative" in last few years..
But they basically are for things that would eventially cause anarchy.. in more than a few things in various degrees..

Anarchy is a Pandoras Box.. You can't have just a little of it.. You get a little you get an open ended trend.. A trend not to "freedom" but to "license".. The U.S. is NOW on a trend toward "license".. in a left wing way.. Socialism is a left wing error, Libertarianism is the same error with a right wing bent..

I am proudly a bit crazy.. as my advertisement implys..

145 posted on 06/08/2005 9:17:03 PM PDT by hosepipe (This propaganda has been ok'ed me to included some fully orbed hyperbole....)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 144 | View Replies]

To: hosepipe

More than a bit.


146 posted on 06/09/2005 7:33:41 AM PDT by P_A_I
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 145 | View Replies]


Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first previous 1-20 ... 81-100101-120121-140141-146 last

Disclaimer: Opinions posted on Free Republic are those of the individual posters and do not necessarily represent the opinion of Free Republic or its management. All materials posted herein are protected by copyright law and the exemption for fair use of copyrighted works.

Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

FreeRepublic, LLC, PO BOX 9771, FRESNO, CA 93794
FreeRepublic.com is powered by software copyright 2000-2008 John Robinson