Posted on 06/06/2003 9:46:51 AM PDT by Luke Skyfreeper
Years go by, and the abortion struggle rages on.
I would like to suggest that the following doctrine is a basis for an uneasy resolution to the political conflict; one that may eventually come to be accepted by all.
Abortion should be legal, but only up to a certain date. We need to define, as best as we can, when we are dealing with a human being.
The current definition of the law afford NO recognition that a developing child is a human being until the moment that child leaves his or her mother's womb. Anyone who pays the faintest attention to what we know through medical science can readily recognize that, at full term, this is far, far too late.
If a developing child is old enough to survive outside of the womb, even with medical assistance, then it's a human being. Obviously.
If the developing child is old enough to feel pain, regardless of whether or not an anesthetic is administered, then it is developed enough to be a human being, and destroying the said developing child must be illegal.
Practically, this means that for humane reasons, all abortions after a certain date (somewhere between 8 and 24 weeks) should be made illegal. This is only humane, and even 8 weeks would allow more than a month for decision making and getting an abortion appointment (although I suspect that a medical consensus would put the development of pain later than that).
The vast majority of abortions already take place before 24 weeks now. However, it is currently legal to destroy developing children at any stage of development, as long as at least part of the child is still inside the mother's body.
I believe this is the basis of the solution to the abortion problem. Part B is that accurate information must be provided to women considering an abortion. Potential adverse effects must be covered, and other options, including adoption, must be adequately presented. A waiting period may also be appropriate.
None of these takes away choice. The choice is still there whether to have a baby or have an abortion.
One can therefore be pro-choice and pro-life at the same time.
I also argue for use of the term "developing child" (which is intuitive, completely accurate and fully descriptive) rather than use of the term "fetus."
Political wars are won and lost on the choice of words.
What you're failing to consider is that you push the same button every time you have sex without contraception. Lots of pregnancies end in miscarriages. These miscarriages could be prevented by celibacy. Does that mean that having sex, resulting in a miscarriage, is morally equivalent to an elective abortion?
And yet there are lots of kids running around whose mommies were taking the pill. They didn't all mis-dose themselves.
There will be failures.
Therefore, if the moral issue begins with the fertilized egg, being on the pill is not the moral equivalent of abortion.
Of course, the moral issue is the fertilized egg. It is a new creation, a new soul God has blessed us with.
And how do we welcome this? With a uterus chemically altered to be inhospitable to life., resulting in the demise of the new life.
Maybe this never happens to you and your wife. Maybe it only happens to less than 1 per cent of couples who use the pill. But if it does happen, then you are morally responsible for the choices you have made. Without your intervention the baby would have lived. You are responsible for its death.
So, what odds do you want?
SD
As I stated near the beginning, there is no "moment" where this becomes true, it is a continuum from a fertlized egg to a newborn infant. During the early stages the fertlized egg is not even in the womb. Once in the womb it is still an unrecognizable blob of microscopic size. The fact that it will keep growing has little moral or legal significance.
Nice try. Next time try to contemplate the difference between natural body function and the body re-acting to chemicals given to it for the express purpose of preventing a new life from implanting.
Can you truly not see the difference that your actions make? You choose to take this pill, you live with the consequences. That includes being guilty for taking a life.
Your argument is the same as arguing that since people die every day by accident or natural causes, it is OK to kill someone.
SD
Later, dude. I have no desire to continue debating someone as depraved as you are here.
And when one person has the power of life or death over another, why does it make a difference whether they are a judge, a bureaucrat, a doctor, or a parent?
Not everyone takes 'the Pill' for contraception. My wife takes it because she has severe endometriosis and is immobilized with pain 8-10 days per month if she doesn't take it. It's medicine to treat her condition. Does a side-effect of medicine taken for other reasons still equate to infanticide in your eyes?
Secondly, yes, spontaneous miscarriage is a natural event. But it is still avoidable. Have you done everything possible to avoid causing such an event (i.e., abstained from sex altogether)?
Your argument is the same as arguing that since people die every day by accident or natural causes, it is OK to kill someone.
No, my argument is the same as arguing that I can drive my children around in the car even though I know there's a non-zero chance that my choice will result in their deaths due to a car accident. If that happens, you cannot accuse me of murder because there was no intent for a life to end.
This is a useless criteria for public policy. PETA looks at a chimpanzee or even a fish an sees "human characteristics" (though, interestingly enough, they don't seem to see them in unborn humans). I see human characteristics in a fertilized egg. Michael Tooley doesn't see them until an infant is about 2 years-old. This doesn't help to draw an objective line at all.
If so, those trigger my emotion of empathy and I want to protect it.
This is even less reliable. Some racists have no empathy for people of other ethnic groups and, using similar logic, often think of them as "less than human". "What do you think?" is how conservatives should approach issues. Leave "How do you feel?" to liberals.
The wrong way to approach this issue is to decide how you "feel" about abortion socially and then go out and try to find criteria to justify your feelings. Think about the issue and make up your mind. Thinking about it changed my mind.
As the human characteristics strengthen, I want to increase protection and sanctions for killing the fetus.
What "human characeristics"? Which one's are important? When do you have enough of them to be protected from execution at the whim of another? This criteria raises as many questions as it answers.
You have it exactly backwards. The language used to justify killing a fetus, namely that which makes the fetus something less than human and therefore killable, is the same type of language used by genocidal governments to justify killing off ethnic groups declared to be subhuman. Government should exist primarily to protect individual rights and lives - and a fetus is an individual with the same right to exist as its mother.
Not Akira Kurosawa's "The Hidden Fortress"?
Postfertilization Effects of Oral Contraceptives and Their Relationship to Informed Consent
Arch Fam Med. 2000;9:126-133.
|
Our analysis of the evidence involved a review of the abstracts of all studies of OCs published since 1970 available on MEDLINE that discussed the commonly used OCs, including low-dose (<50 µg of estrogen) phasic combined oral contraceptives (COCs), low-dose monophasic COCs, and progestin-only OCs (progestin-only pills [POPs]). We also reviewed the patient handouts provided by OC manufacturers and the most recent editions of several medical textbooks and reference books.
Since there is variability in the definitions and use of terminology in reproductive medicine, we used the American Academy of Obstetrics and Gynecology Committee on Ethics' definitions for fertilization, implantation, embryo, and preembryo.16 Preembryo is a general term that includes the human developmental stages that occur after fertilization but prior to the appearance of the primitive streak about 14 days after fertilization. From that point until the end of the eighth week after fertilization, the term embryo is used. Implantation is the process whereby the preembryo attaches to the endometrial lining of the uterus. This process begins 5 to 7 days after fertilization and may last several days. For this review, we defined postfertilization effects to include mechanisms of action that operate after fertilization to prevent a clinically recognized intrauterine pregnancy. We looked specifically for studies referencing any postfertilization effects of OCs. When many studies indicated similar findings, we listed the most recent or most methodologically sound references or other systematic or general reviews of particular subjects.
|
Breakthrough ovulation rates vary by the form and the dose of the OC used.2, 10, 12, 18, 22 With OCs, breakthrough ovulation is more likely with lower doses of estrogen and with imperfect rather than perfect use.10, 12, 16-17,23-25 Perfect use of OCs implies taking them consistently and correctly (ie, in the correct order, on time, each and every day, and without other medications that might diminish the effectiveness of OCs). Typical use is described as the full range of usage patterns for OCs that actually occur in women.1, 11-12,18 While some smaller studies that evaluated small numbers of women for 6 or fewer cycles have reported breakthrough ovulation rates of near 0, studies that evaluated women for at least 6 cycles demonstrated ovulation rates ranging from 1.7%25 to 28.6%23 per cycle. For POPs, reported breakthrough ovulation rates range from 33%26 to 65%.20, 27-28
Obviously, breakthrough ovulation can result in unintended pregnancy1, 17-18; however, the pregnancy rates with typical use vary widely and are often underestimated.29 Unadjusted analyses of unintended pregnancies while using COCs report rates of 0.1 to 1.0 per 100 woman-years of use in perfect use and 3 per 100 woman-years in the first year of typical use.1, 10, 12, 17-18,20 Most of these data do not account for elective abortions. One national analysis that accounted for the underreporting of elective abortions estimated that the unintended pregnancy rates during the first year of OC use were 4% for "good compliers," 8% for "poor compliers," and up to 29% for some users.29 Rates of pregnancy are higher with POPs than with COCs.1, 17-18 Unadjusted analyses of pregnancies while taking POPs reported rates of 0.5 to 1.0 per 100 woman-years of perfect use and 3 to 7 per 100 woman-years in the first year of typical use.1, 10, 12, 17-18,20 However, these rates have not been adjusted for elective abortions and are almost certainly underestimated.29 Progestin-only pills are reported to have potent effects on both cervical mucus and the endometrium.19-21,30-31 While this has led to speculation that "the principal mode of action is . . . to make the cervical mucus hostile to the transport of the sperm,"17 animal model data32 and data on ectopic pregnancy rates (reviewed below) suggest that postfertilization effects also play a role.
In theory, postfertilization effects of OCs could involve any 1 or more of the following 3 mechanisms of action: (1) A postfertilization preimplantation effect would consist of a slower transport of the preembryo through the fallopian tube, preventing the preembryo from implanting in the uterus; this could result either in the unrecognized loss of the preembryo or in an ectopic (tubal) pregnancy if the preembryo had slower tubal transport and ended up implanting in the fallopian tube. (2) A peri-implantation effect would be the alteration of the endometrium, such that a preembryo that reached the uterus was unable to successfully implant into the endometrial lining of the uterus. (3) A postimplantation effect could result from alteration of the endometrium not sufficient to prevent implantation but unfavorable for maintenance of the pregnancy; a preembryo or embryo already implanted in the endometrial lining of the uterus would be unable to maintain itself long enough to result in a clinically recognized pregnancy.
EVIDENCE FOR POSTFERTILIZATION EFFECTS
|
Direct evidence of a postimplantation effect on the preembryo or embryo prior to clinically recognized pregnancy would require measurement with ultrasensitive assays for human chorionic gonadotropin (-HCG) or other pregnancy-related hormones.40 Although ultrasensitive assays for -HCG have been done with normally fertile women not using OCs,41-44 as well as with women using nonhormonal methods of contraception,45 we could find no such studies in women using OCs. Despite the lack of these data, at least 3 lines of evidence have been suggested to support the hypothesis that 1 or more postfertilization effects are operative in at least some women taking OCs. Using a standard quality of evidence table46 (Table 1), we graded the available evidence.
|
Endometrial Changes That May Affect Endometrial Receptivity
Oral contraceptives directly affect the endometrium.1, 10, 12, 20-21 These effects have been presumed to render the endometrium relatively inhospitable to implantation or to the maintenance of the preembryo or embryo prior to clinically recognized pregnancy by producing a predecidual or decidualized endometrial bed with diminished thickness and with widely spaced, exhausted, and atrophied glands; by altering the cellular structure of the endometrium, leading to the production of areas of edema alternating with areas of dense cellularity18, 20-21; and by altering the biochemical and protein composition of the endometrium.47
Although these changes are consistently seen in women taking OCs, there is currently no direct evidence to link these changes to preembryo or embryo loss in women taking OCs. However, this hypothesized postfertilization effect seems to be so well accepted that in many medical articles and textbooks it has been explicitly listed as the third mechanism of OCs (after suppressing ovulation and prefertilization effects).1, 10, 17-18 For example, the Food and Drug Administrationapproved product information for OCs in the Physicians' Desk Reference states,
Although the primary mechanism of this action is inhibition of ovulation, other alterations include changes in the cervical mucus, which increase the difficulty of sperm entry into the uterus, and changes in the endometrium, which reduce the likelihood of implantation.11
An independent clinical pharmaceutical reference also contains this assertion.12 We considered this level III (poor to good) evidence (Table 1).
To assess the clinical significance of an altered endometrium, it was helpful to examine data that compared endometrial thickness with the receptivity of the endometrium to preembryos during in vitro fertilization procedures. Magnetic resonance imaging scans of the uteri of women reveal that the OC users have endometrial linings that are consistently thinner than the endometrial linings of nonusers,48-50 up to 58% thinner.51 Of the first 4 ultrasound studies published, the first did not find a relationship between endometrial thickness and in vitro fertilization implantation rates52; however, subsequent studies noted a trend,53-54 and one demonstrated that a decreased thickness of the endometrium decreased the likelihood of implantation.55 Larger, more recent, and more technically sophisticated studies56-65 all concluded that endometrial thickness is related to the functional receptivity of the endometrium. Furthermore, when the endometrial lining becomes too thin, then implantation does not occur.56-58,64-65 The minimal endometrial thickness required to maintain a pregnancy in patients undergoing in vitro fertilization has been reported, ranging from 5 mm55 to 9 mm65 to 13 mm,53 whereas the average endometrial thickness in women taking OCs is 1.1 mm.50 These data would seem to lend credence to the Food and Drug Administrationapproved statements that " . . . changes in the endometrium . . . reduce the likelihood of implantation."11 We considered this level II.2 (good to very good) evidence (Table 1).
Integrin Changes Affecting Fallopial Tube and Endometrial Receptivity for Implantation
Integrins are a family of cell adhesion molecules that are accepted as markers of uterine receptivity for implantation.66-67 Temporal and spatial expression of these endometrial peptides is believed to contribute to the establishment and maintenance of a cyclical endometrial receptivity. Three cycle-dependent integrins (11, 41, V3) have been shown to be " . . . coexpressed apparently only for a brief interval of the cycle that corresponds with the putative window of maximal uterine receptivity" and " . . . have emerged as reliable markers of normal fertility."68 Of these 3, the V3 integrin seems "to be an excellent marker to study the molecular events leading to the establishment of uterine receptivity and successful implantation."68-69 These 3 integrins are conspicuously absent in the endometrium of most patients with luteal phase deficiency, endometriosis, and unexplained infertility.68
In addition, integrin expression is significantly changed by OCs. Integrins have been compared using endometrial biopsy specimens from normally cycling women and women taking OCs. In most OC users, the normal patterns of expression of the integrins are grossly altered, leading Somkuti et al68 to conclude that the OC-induced integrin changes observed in the endometrium have functional significance and provide evidence that reduced endometrial receptivity does indeed contribute to the contraceptive efficacy of OCs. They hypothesized that the sex steroids in OCs alter the expression of these integrins through cytokines and therefore predispose to failure of implantation or loss of the preembryo or embryo after implantation. We considered this level II.3 (good) evidence (Table 1).
Integrins have also been identified in the fallopian tube.69 Of interest, the V subunit is expressed in the fallopian tube epithelium throughout the cycle, but the 3 subunit is only upregulated during the period of endometrial receptivity. Therefore, it has now been postulated that the normal tubal epithelium also has an implantation window that " . . . affords the opportunity for trophoblast attachment should a 5-7 day preembryo be unduly retained in the tube."69 As discussed earlier, one of the postulated actions of the OCs is a slowing of tubal peristalsis (via smooth muscle relaxation)70; therefore, a reduction in tubal peristalsis that is associated with an upregulation of the V3 integrin in the epithelium of the fallopian tube could theoretically lead to an increased risk of ectopic pregnancies in women taking OCs.
If breakthrough ovulation occurs while using the COC, then to some extent ovarian and blastocyst steroidogenesis could theoretically "turn on" the endometrium, causing it to normalize prior to implantation in the ovulatory cycle. However, after discontinuing use of COCs, it usually takes several cycles for a woman's menstrual flow to approach the volume of women who have not taken hormonal contraception,71 suggesting that the endometrium is slow to recover from its COC-induced atrophy. Furthermore, in women who have ovulated secondary to missing 2 low-dose COCs, the endometrium in the luteal phase of the ovulatory cycle has been found to be nonsecretory.23
Increased Extrauterine Pregnancy to Intrauterine Pregnancy Ratio
If the action(s) of OCs on the fallopian tube and endometrium were such as to have no postfertilization effects, then the reduction in the rate of intrauterine pregnancies in women taking OCs should be proportional to the reduction in the rate of extrauterine pregnancies in women taking OCs. If the effect of OCs is to increase the extrauterine-to-intrauterine pregnancy ratio, this would indicate that one or more postfertilization effects are operating. All published data that we could review indicated that the ratio of extrauterine-to-intrauterine pregnancies is increased for women taking OCs and exceeds that expected among control groups of pregnant women not currently using OCs. These case-controlled series come from 33 centers in 17 countries and include more than 2800 cases and controls.72-77 The odds ratios in these studies ranged from 1.7 (95% confidence interval [CI], 1.1-2.5)72 to 1.8 (95% CI, 0.9-3.4)73 to 4.3 (95% CI, 1.5-12.6)74 to 4.5 (95% CI, 2.1-9.6)75 to 13.9 (95% CI, 1.8-108.3).76 The letter by Job-Spira et al74 seems to represent the same data set of 279 cases and controls as the study by Coste et al.76 The meta-analysis by Mol et al73 includes 2 of the publications,72, 75 but one of these may include women taking POPs.72 Therefore, of the 5 publications, only 2 allow review of the association of COCs with ectopic pregnancy.75-76 These 2 studies from 7 maternity hospitals in Paris, France, and 3 in Sweden involved 484 women with ectopic pregnancies and 289 pregnant controls and suggest that at least some protection against intrauterine pregnancy is provided via postfertilization preimplantation effects. We recognize that studies that have used nonpregnant controls have not shown a risk of increased ectopic pregnancy for users of COCs. In our review, we restricted our analysis to studies using pregnant controls, because we concur with researchers73, 76 in this field that " . . . when considering the situation where a woman became pregnant during contraceptive use, one should focus on pregnant controls."73 Therefore, COC use seems to be associated with an increased risk of ectopic implantation or unrecognized loss of preembryos. We considered this level II.2 (good to very good) evidence (Table 1).
Ectopic pregnancy is a particular form of postfertilization loss that involves substantial risks to the woman, and thus the absolute risk of ectopic pregnancy for women taking OCs will be of interest to clinicians and patients. Converting a relative risk of ectopic pregnancy to an absolute risk has many inherent difficulties that have been reviewed elsewhere.78 Nevertheless, adapting the method suggested by Franks et al78 would allow one to predict that the ectopic pregnancy rate for women taking OCs would be the product of 3 factors: (1) the overall pregnancy rate per 1000 woman-years among those taking OCs, (2) the proportion of extrauterine pregnancies compared with all pregnancies for a comparable control population not taking OCs, and (3) the relative risk for ectopic pregnancy in women taking OCs compared with the control population, which may be estimated by the odds ratio from case-control studies. For factor 1, Potter29 suggests 40 for good compliers and 80 for poor compliers. For factor 2, the proportion of ectopic pregnancies in the 1990s is estimated to range from 1 in every 5679 to 6480-81 pregnancies (0.0156 to 0.0179). A reasonable range for factor 3 would be 1.1 to 13.9, based on the studies discussed above. This model would predict an absolute risk ranging from 0.7 (40 x 0.0156 x 1.1) to 19.9 (80 x 0.0179 x 13.9) ectopic pregnancies per 1000 woman-years. We could only find one study, from Zimbabwe, which reported an absolute risk of ectopic pregnancy in women taking OCs of 0.582 per 1000 woman-years.
The risk of ectopic pregnancy is higher with POPs, and ectopic pregnancy has been discussed at length by a number of investigators as a clinically significant potential complication of POPs.82-84 The odds ratio of an extrauterine pregnancy for a woman taking a POP (compared with pregnant controls) was reported in only one study and was 79.1 (95% CI, 8.5-735.1).74 Assuming an overall clinical pregnancy rate of 30 to 70 per 1000 woman-years, this equates to a predicted absolute risk of 4 to 99 ectopic pregnancies per 1000 woman-years ([30 or 70] x [0.0156 or 0.0179] x [8.5 or 79.1]) in women taking POPs. This is reasonably concordant with absolute rates of ectopic pregnancy in women taking POPs, which have been reported to range from about 382-83,85 to about 2084, 86 per 1000 woman-years.
Data from case-controlled series demonstrate that women with clinically recognized pregnancy are no more or less likely to miscarry based on whether they were taking an OC after their pregnancy was clinically recognized.87-90 However, the epidemiology, biology, and recognized risk factors of clinically recognized embryo or fetal loss (spontaneous abortion after clinically recognized pregnancy) do not seem to apply to early (unrecognized) preembryo or embryo loss, as the available evidence suggests that the mechanisms of early establishment and maintenance of pregnancy and later maintenance of pregnancy are qualitatively and substantially different.90
|
Despite the evidence, which suggests that postfertilization effects for OCs are operational at least some of the time, and the fact that a postfertilization mechanism for OCs is described in the Physicians' Desk Reference,11 in Drug Facts and Comparisons,12 and in most standard gynecologic, family practice, nursing, and public health textbooks, we anecdotally find that few physicians or patients are aware of this possibility. Therefore, we believe that the potential for postfertilization effects is probably not routinely presented to patients as part of their informed consent to use an OC. Furthermore, it is of concern to us that only one of the many OC patient information handouts we and others5 have reviewed, including those produced by the OC manufacturers, mentions the possible postfertilization mechanism, despite the fact that this information is nearly always included in the professional labeling of these same OCs.
Since there is evidence to support the existence of postfertilization effects and because it is impossible to know in advance which patients would find the potential for this effect objectionable, we believe that the lack of information regarding postfertilization effects in patient information materials about OCs represents a potential failure to provide complete informed consent. Furthermore, if this mechanism of an OC violates the moral requirements of a woman, then failure to disclose this information seriously jeopardizes her autonomy. If information about the mechanism of an OC is deliberately withheld or misstated, then an unethical deception occurs. Failure to disclose information that might lead a patient to choose a different method of treatment is generally considered to be unethical.12-13 Therefore, it seems clear to us that failure to inform patients of a possible postfertilization mechanism of an OC is a failure to provide informed consent.
|
However, the objective presentation of the potential for postfertilization effects of OCs may be complex; there are a variety of potential interpretations of the postfertilization effects depending on which aspect is emphasized: (1) One could state that OCs may significantly reduce the absolute risk per woman-year of any possible postfertilization loss in the same way that they reduce the absolute clinical pregnancy rate.78 For some women or medical personnel who believe that human life begins at fertilization, this view might render OCs, even with postfertilization loss, morally acceptable. (2) One could emphasize that once fertilization has occurred, OCs may cause at least an occasional postfertilization loss, regardless of the rate of fertilization. For some women or medical personnel who believe that human life begins at fertilization, the view that any postfertilization loss could be attributed to the effects of OCs and therefore could be considered induced rather than natural may render OCs morally unacceptable to use, even if the absolute frequency of such an event is very low.
Medical colleagues have suggested to us that postfertilization loss attributed to OCs would not need to be included in informed consent until it is either definitely proven to exist or proven to be a common event. However, rare but important events are an essential part of other informed consent discussions in medicine, primarily when the rare possibility would be judged by the patient to be important. For example, anesthesia-related deaths are extremely rare for elective surgery (<1:25,000 cases); nevertheless, it is considered appropriate and legally necessary to discuss this rare possibility with patients before such surgery because the possibility of death is so important. Therefore, for women to whom the induced loss of a preembryo or embryo is important, failure to discuss this possibility, even if the possibility is judged to be remote, would be a failure of informed consent. Others feel that an overemphasis of possible postfertilization effects might make women choose a less-effective method of contraception and therefore increase the incidence of unplanned pregnancy. Both of these views fail to acknowledge the value of a woman's autonomy in making decisions based on informed consent. During informed consent discussions, overemphasis of any single possible risk may not result in appropriate informed consent; however, neither does choosing to not mention the possible risk result in adequate informed consent. Therefore, discussion of this potential risk should occur and should be kept within the perspective of the available medical evidence.
One possible approach to this complex issue might be to inquire of the patient whether she desires this information. The physician or provider might say, for example: "Most of the time, the pill acts by preventing an egg from forming. This prevents pregnancy. However, women on the pill can still sometimes get pregnant. Some doctors think that the pill may cause the loss of some of these pregnancies very early in the pregnancy, before you would even know you were pregnant. Would knowing more about this possibility be important to you in your decision about whether to use the pill?"
If the answer is yes, further explanation of the issues would be indicated and should occur in terms that are as understandable as possible. Proper informed consent requires patient and physician comprehension of information, the disclosure of this information, and the sharing of interpretations.14-15 If any mechanism of any OC violates the morals of any particular woman, the failure of the physician or care provider to disclose this information would effectively eliminate the likelihood that the woman's consent was truly informed13-14,93 and would seriously jeopardize her autonomy.13
Furthermore, there is a potential for negative psychological impact on women who believe human life begins at fertilization, who have not been given informed consent about OCs, and who later learn of the potential for postfertilization effects of OCs.94 The responses to this could include disappointment, anger, guilt, sadness, anger, rage, depression, or a sense of having been violated by the provider.5 Further research is necessary to identify the exact frequency of postfertilization effects of OCs.
|
|
We thank John R. Hartman, MD, Chris Kahlenborn, MD, G. Gayle Stephens, MD, William Toffler, MD, and Randy Alcorn, MS, for their help with conceptual development of this article and for identifying important references.
Reprints: Joseph B. Stanford, MD, MSPH, Department of Family and Preventive Medicine, University of Utah, 50 North Medical Dr, Salt Lake City, UT 84132 (e-mail: jstanford@dfpm.utah.edu).
From the Department of Family Medicine, University of South Florida, Kissimmee (Dr Larimore), and Department of Family and Preventive Medicine, University of Utah, Salt Lake City (Dr Stanford).
|
RELATED ARTICLES IN ARCHIVES OF FAMILY MEDICINE
Postfertilization Effects of Oral Contraceptives and Their Relationship to Informed Consent
Walter L. Larimore
Arch Fam Med. 2000;9:133.
The Archives of Family Medicine Continuing Medical Education Program
Arch Fam Med. 2000;9:175-177.
THIS ARTICLE HAS BEEN CITED BY OTHER ARTICLES
Informed Consent for Postfertilization Effects of Hormonal and Surgical Forms of Birth Control for Women
Sherfey et al.
Arch Fam Med 2000;9:690-691.
Ectopic pregnancy with oral contraceptive use has been overlooked
Larimore and Stanford
BMJ 2000;321:450-450.
|
It has all the moral significance in the world. If a brain dead person in a coma and on life support would recover after about nine months if they were only left on life support, I doubt most people would support treating brain death as legal death or support pulling such people off of life support. Where and what you will be tomorrow matters. Indeed, you can't fully explain why murder is as wrong as it is without taking that into account (consider mercy killings, brain death, the death of the elderly vs. promising children, etc.).
So if a majority of Americans decreed that we should kill all of a certain ethnic group, that would be acceptable?
I don't care to empower government to overrule individual citizens in such important and personal matters.
So it becomes a personal matter to kill a fetus. Where does the dehumanization stop, eh?
I am very familiar with the disease. No, medicine taken for a legitimate reason that has a side effect is not the same thing as taking medicine for the "side effect." Are you really this un-versed in basic morality?
Likewise, a woman can undergo radiation or chemotherepy to combat cancer even if that results in the demise of any baby she may be carrying. This does not mean that a woman is morally justified in undergoing radiation therepy in order to kill her baby.
Secondly, yes, spontaneous miscarriage is a natural event. But it is still avoidable. Have you done everything possible to avoid causing such an event (i.e., abstained from sex altogether)?
Huh? If God grants a couple a new baby and then they lose it through no fault of their own, this is not equivalent to desiring and acting to make sure a woman will lose any baby she may be carrying.
The concept is rather simple -- birth control causes miscarriage. Taking birth control then causes miscarriage. It is an act with a consequence. We are responsible for our acts. We don't shrug our shoulders and say, "oh well, people die all the time."
No, my argument is the same as arguing that I can drive my children around in the car even though I know there's a non-zero chance that my choice will result in their deaths due to a car accident. If that happens, you cannot accuse me of murder because there was no intent for a life to end.
Hello? The woman who takes birth control to "control" her fertility does indeed intend for the pill to work. That she does not know how it works or is unwilling to accept the truth is not an excuse. She intends that she not get pregnant no matter what. She intends to ingest the pill and benefit from its effects.
So she has to live with the moral consequences of her acts.
SD
Disclaimer: Opinions posted on Free Republic are those of the individual posters and do not necessarily represent the opinion of Free Republic or its management. All materials posted herein are protected by copyright law and the exemption for fair use of copyrighted works.